Difference between revisions of "Directory:Jon Awbrey/Papers/Peirce's 1870 Logic Of Relatives"

MyWikiBiz, Author Your Legacy — Sunday December 01, 2024
Jump to navigationJump to search
 
(505 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 
{{DISPLAYTITLE:Peirce's 1870 Logic Of Relatives}}
 
{{DISPLAYTITLE:Peirce's 1870 Logic Of Relatives}}
'''Author's Note.''' The text that follows is a collection of notes that will eventually be developed into a paper on [[Charles Sanders Peirce]]'s [[Logic of Relatives (1870)|1870 memoir on the logic of relative terms]]. [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] 06:06, 8 October 2007 (PDT)
+
'''Note.''' The MathJax parser is not rendering this page properly.<br>Until it can be fixed please see the [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Peirce's_1870_Logic_Of_Relatives InterSciWiki version].
  
----
+
'''Author: [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]]'''
  
==Selection 1==
+
Peirce's text employs lower case letters for logical terms of general reference and upper case letters for logical terms of individual reference.&nbsp; General terms fall into types &mdash; absolute terms, dyadic relative terms, higher adic relative terms &mdash; and Peirce employs different typefaces to distinguish these.&nbsp; The following Tables indicate the typefaces that are used in the text below for Peirce's examples of general terms.
 +
 
 +
<br>
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|+ <math>\text{Absolute Terms (Monadic Relatives)}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{ll}
 +
\mathrm{a}. & \text{animal}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{b}. & \text{black}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{f}. & \text{Frenchman}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{h}. & \text{horse}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{m}. & \text{man}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{p}. & \text{President of the United States Senate}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{r}. & \text{rich person}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{u}. & \text{violinist}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{v}. & \text{Vice-President of the United States}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{w}. & \text{woman}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
<blockquote>
+
<br>
<p>The letters of the alphabet will denote logical signs.</p>
 
  
<p>Now logical terms are of three grand classes.</p>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|+ <math>\text{Simple Relative Terms (Dyadic Relatives)}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{ll}
 +
\mathit{a}. & \text{enemy}
 +
\\
 +
\mathit{b}. & \text{benefactor}
 +
\\
 +
\mathit{c}. & \text{conqueror}
 +
\\
 +
\mathit{e}. & \text{emperor}
 +
\\
 +
\mathit{h}. & \text{husband}
 +
\\
 +
\mathit{l}. & \text{lover}
 +
\\
 +
\mathit{m}. & \text{mother}
 +
\\
 +
\mathit{n}. & \text{not}
 +
\\
 +
\mathit{o}. & \text{owner}
 +
\\
 +
\mathit{s}. & \text{servant}
 +
\\
 +
\mathit{w}. & \text{wife}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
<p>The first embraces those whose logical form involves only the conception of quality, and which therefore represent a thing simply as "a ---".  These discriminate objects in the most rudimentary way, which does not involve any consciousness of discrimination.  They regard an object as it is in itself as ''such'' (''quale'');  for example, as horse, tree, or man.  These are ''absolute terms''.</p>
+
<br>
  
<p>The second class embraces terms whose logical form involves the conception of relation, and which require the addition of another term to complete the denotation.  These discriminate objects with a distinct consciousness of discrimination. They regard an object as over against another, that is as relative;  as father of, lover of, or servant of.  These are ''simple relative terms''.</p>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|+ <math>\text{Conjugative Terms (Higher Adic Relatives)}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{ll}
 +
\mathfrak{b}. & \text{betrayer to ------ of ------}
 +
\\
 +
\mathfrak{g}. & \text{giver to ------ of ------}
 +
\\
 +
\mathfrak{t}. & \text{transferrer from ------ to ------}
 +
\\
 +
\mathfrak{w}. & \text{winner over of ------ to ------ from ------}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
<p>The third class embraces terms whose logical form involves the conception of bringing things into relation, and which require the addition of more than one term to complete the denotation.  They discriminate not only with consciousness of discrimination, but with consciousness of its origin.  They regard  an object as medium or third between two others, that is as conjugative;  as giver of --- to ---, or buyer of --- for --- from ---.  These may be termed ''conjugative terms''.</p>
+
<br>
  
<p>The conjugative term involves the conception of ''third'', the relative that of second or ''other'', the absolute term simply considers ''an'' objectNo fourth class of terms exists involving the conception of ''fourth'', because when that of ''third'' is introduced, since it involves the conception of bringing objects into relation, all higher numbers are given at once, inasmuch as the conception of bringing objects into relation is independent of the number of members of the relationship.  Whether this ''reason'' for the fact that there is no fourth class of terms fundamentally different from the third is satisfactory of not, the fact itself is made perfectly evident by the study of the logic of relatives. (Peirce, CP 3.63).</p>
+
Individual terms are taken to denote individual entities falling under a general term.  Peirce uses upper case Roman letters for individual terms, for example, the individual horses <math>\mathrm{H}, \mathrm{H}^{\prime}, \mathrm{H}^{\prime\prime}</math> falling under the general term <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math> for ''horse''.
</blockquote>
 
  
I am going to experiment with an interlacing commentary on Peirce's 1870 "Logic of Relatives" paper, revisiting some critical transitions from several different angles and calling attention to a variety of puzzles, problems, and potentials that are not so often remarked or tapped.
+
The path to understanding Peirce's system and its wider implications for logic can be smoothed by paraphrasing his notations in a variety of contemporary mathematical formalisms, while preserving the semantics as much as possible.  Remaining faithful to Peirce's orthography while adding parallel sets of stylistic conventions will, however, demand close attention to typography-in-context.  Current style sheets for mathematical texts specify italics for mathematical variables, with upper case letters for sets and lower case letters for individuals.  So we need to keep an eye out for the difference between the individual <math>\mathrm{X}\!</math> of the genus <math>\mathrm{x}\!</math> and the element <math>x\!</math> of the set <math>X\!</math> as we pass between the two styles of text.
  
What strikes me about the initial installment this time around is its use of a certain pattern of argument that I can recognize as invoking a "closure principle", and this is a figure of reasoning that Peirce uses in three other places:  his discussion of "[[continuous predicate]]s", his definition of [[sign relation]]s, and in the [[pragmatic maxim]] itself.
+
__TOC__
  
One might also call attention to the following two statements:
+
==Selection 1==
  
<blockquote>
+
===Use of the Letters===
Now logical terms are of three grand classes.
 
</blockquote>
 
  
<blockquote>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
No fourth class of terms exists involving the conception of ''fourth'', because when that of ''third'' is introduced, since it involves the conception of bringing objects into relation, all higher numbers are given at once, inasmuch as the conception of bringing objects into relation is independent of the number of members of the relationship.
+
|
</blockquote>
+
<p>The letters of the alphabet will denote logical signs.</p>
  
==Selection 2==
+
<p>Now logical terms are of three grand classes.</p>
  
<blockquote>
+
<p>The first embraces those whose logical form involves only the conception of quality, and which therefore represent a thing simply as &ldquo;a&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash;&rdquo;.  These discriminate objects in the most rudimentary way, which does not involve any consciousness of discrimination.  They regard an object as it is in itself as ''such'' (''quale'');  for example, as horse, tree, or man.  These are ''absolute terms''.</p>
<p>'''Numbers Corresponding to Letters'''</p>
 
  
<p>I propose to use the term "universe" to denote that class of individuals ''about'' which alone the whole discourse is understood to runThe universe, therefore, in this sense, as in Mr.&nbsp;De&nbsp;Morgan's, is different on different occasions. In this sense, moreover, discourse may run upon something which is not a subjective part of the universe;  for instance, upon the qualities or collections of the individuals it contains.</p>
+
<p>The second class embraces terms whose logical form involves the conception of relation, and which require the addition of another term to complete the denotation.  These discriminate objects with a distinct consciousness of discriminationThey regard an object as over against another, that is as relativeas father of, lover of, or servant of.  These are ''simple relative terms''.</p>
  
<p>I propose to assign to all logical terms, numbers;  to an absolute term, the number of individuals it denotes;  to a relative term, the average number of things so related to one individualThus in a universe of perfect men (''men''), the number of "tooth of" would be 32The number of a relative with two correlates would be the average number of things so related to a pair of individuals; and so on for relatives of higher numbers of correlatesI propose to denote the number of a logical term by enclosing the term in square brackets, thus <nowiki>[</nowiki>''t''<nowiki>]</nowiki>.  (Peirce, CP 3.65).</p>
+
<p>The third class embraces terms whose logical form involves the conception of bringing things into relation, and which require the addition of more than one term to complete the denotationThey discriminate not only with consciousness of discrimination, but with consciousness of its originThey regard  an object as medium or third between two others, that is as conjugative;  as giver of&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash; to&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash;, or buyer of&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash; for&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash; from&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash;These may be termed ''conjugative terms''.</p>
</blockquote>
 
  
Peirce's remarks at CP 3.65 are so replete with remarkable ideas, some of them so taken for granted in mathematical discourse that they usually escape explicit mention, and others so suggestive of things to come in a future remote from his time of writing, and yet so smoothly introduced in passing that it's all too easy to overlook their consequential significance, that I can do no better here than to highlight these ideas in other words, whose main advantage is to be a little more jarring to the mind's sensibilities.
+
<p>The conjugative term involves the conception of ''third'', the relative that of second or ''other'', the absolute term simply considers ''an'' object.  No fourth class of terms exists involving the conception of ''fourth'', because when that of ''third'' is introduced, since it involves the conception of bringing objects into relation, all higher numbers are given at once, inasmuch as the conception of bringing objects into relation is independent of the number of members of the relationship.  Whether this ''reason'' for the fact that there is no fourth class of terms fundamentally different from the third is satisfactory or not, the fact itself is made perfectly evident by the study of the logic of relatives.</p>
  
'''Numbers Corresponding to Letters'''
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.63).</p>
# This mapping of letters to numbers, or logical terms to mathematical quantities, is the very core of what "quantification theory" is all about, and definitely more to the point than the mere "innovation" of using distinctive symbols for the so-called "quantifiers".  We will speak of this more later on.
+
|}
# The mapping of logical terms to numerical measures, to express it in current language, would probably be recognizable as some kind of "morphism" or "functor" from a logical domain to a quantitative co-domain.
 
# Notice that Peirce follows the mathematician's usual practice, then and now, of making the status of being an "individual" or a "universal" relative to a discourse in progress. I have come to appreciate more and more of late how radically different this "patchwork" or "piecewise" approach to things is from the way of some philosophers who seem to be content with nothing less than many worlds domination, which means that they are never content and rarely get started toward the solution of any real problem.  Just my observation, I hope you understand.
 
# It is worth noting that Peirce takes the "plural denotation" of terms for granted, or what's the number of a term for, if it could not vary apart from being one or nil?
 
# I also observe that Peirce takes the individual objects of a particular universe of discourse in a "generative" way, not a "totalizing" way, and thus they afford us with the basis for talking freely about collections, constructions, properties, qualities, subsets, and "higher types", as the phrase is mint.
 
  
==Selection 3==
+
I am going to experiment with an interlacing commentary on Peirce's 1870 &ldquo;Logic of Relatives&rdquo; paper, revisiting some critical transitions from several different angles and calling attention to a variety of puzzles, problems, and potentials that are not so often remarked or tapped.
  
<blockquote>
+
What strikes me about the initial installment this time around is its use of a certain pattern of argument that I can recognize as invoking a ''closure principle'', and this is a figure of reasoning that Peirce uses in three other places:  his discussion of [[continuous predicates]], his definition of [[sign relations]], and in the [[pragmatic maxim]] itself.
<p>'''The Signs of Inclusion, Equality, Etc.'''</p>
 
  
<p>I shall follow Boole in taking the sign of equality to signify identity.  Thus, if v denotes the Vice-President of the United States, and p the President of the Senate of the United States,</p>
+
One might also call attention to the following two statements:
  
<p>v = p</p>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 +
|
 +
<p>Now logical terms are of three grand classes.</p>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>No fourth class of terms exists involving the conception of ''fourth'', because when that of ''third'' is introduced, since it involves the conception of bringing objects into relation, all higher numbers are given at once, inasmuch as the conception of bringing objects into relation is independent of the number of members of the relationship.</p>
 +
|}
  
<p>means that every Vice-President of the United States is President of the Senate, and every President of the United States Senate is Vice-President.</p>
+
==Selection 2==
  
<p>The sign "less than" is to be so taken that</p>
+
===Numbers Corresponding to Letters===
  
<p>f &lt; m</p>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 +
|
 +
<p>I propose to use the term &ldquo;universe&rdquo; to denote that class of individuals ''about'' which alone the whole discourse is understood to run.  The universe, therefore, in this sense, as in Mr.&nbsp;De&nbsp;Morgan's, is different on different occasions.  In this sense, moreover, discourse may run upon something which is not a subjective part of the universe; for instance, upon the qualities or collections of the individuals it contains.</p>
  
<p>means that every Frenchman is a man, but there are men besides Frenchmen.</p>
+
<p>I propose to assign to all logical terms, numbers;  to an absolute term, the number of individuals it denotes;  to a relative term, the average number of things so related to one individual.  Thus in a universe of perfect men (''men''), the number of &ldquo;tooth of&rdquo; would be 32.  The number of a relative with two correlates would be the average number of things so related to a pair of individuals;  and so on for relatives of higher numbers of correlates.  I propose to denote the number of a logical term by enclosing the term in square brackets, thus <math>[t].\!</math></p>
  
<p>Drobisch has used this sign in the same sense.  It will follow from these significations of '=' and '<' that the sign '-<' (or '=<', "as small as") will mean "is". Thus,</p>
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.65).</p>
 +
|}
  
<p>f -< m</p>
+
Peirce's remarks at CP 3.65 are so replete with remarkable ideas, some of them so taken for granted in mathematical discourse that they usually escape explicit mention, and others so suggestive of things to come in a future remote from his time of writing, and yet so smoothly introduced in passing that it's all too easy to overlook their consequential significance, that I can do no better here than to highlight these ideas in other words, whose main advantage is to be a little more jarring to the mind's sensibilities.
  
<p>means "every Frenchman is a man", without saying whether there are any other men or notSo,</p>
+
:* This mapping of letters to numbers, or logical terms to mathematical quantities, is the very core of what "quantification theory" is all about, and definitely more to the point than the mere "innovation" of using distinctive symbols for the so-called "quantifiers".  We will speak of this more later on.
  
<p>'m' -< 'l'</p>
+
:* The mapping of logical terms to numerical measures, to express it in current language, would probably be recognizable as some kind of "morphism" or "functor" from a logical domain to a quantitative co-domain.
  
<p>will mean that every mother of anything is a lover of the same thing;  although this interpretation in some degree anticipates a convention to be made further onThese significations of '=' and '<' plainly conform to the indispensable conditions.  Upon the transitive character of these relations the syllogism depends, for by virtue of it, from</p>
+
:* Notice that Peirce follows the mathematician's usual practice, then and now, of making the status of being an "individual" or a "universal" relative to a discourse in progressI have come to appreciate more and more of late how radically different this "patchwork" or "piecewise" approach to things is from the way of some philosophers who seem to be content with nothing less than many worlds domination, which means that they are never content and rarely get started toward the solution of any real problem.  Just my observation, I hope you understand.
  
<p>f -< m</p>
+
:* It is worth noting that Peirce takes the "plural denotation" of terms for granted, or what's the number of a term for, if it could not vary apart from being one or nil?
  
<p>and</p>
+
:* I also observe that Peirce takes the individual objects of a particular universe of discourse in a "generative" way, not a "totalizing" way, and thus they afford us with the basis for talking freely about collections, constructions, properties, qualities, subsets, and "higher types", as the phrase is mint.
  
<p>m -< a,</p>
+
==Selection 3==
  
<p>we can infer that</p>
+
===The Signs of Inclusion, Equality, Etc.===
  
<p>f -< a;</p>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 +
|
 +
<p>I shall follow Boole in taking the sign of equality to signify identity.  Thus, if <math>\mathrm{v}\!</math> denotes the Vice-President of the United States, and <math>\mathrm{p}~\!</math> the President of the Senate of the United States,</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{v} = \mathrm{p}\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>means that every Vice-President of the United States is President of the Senate, and every President of the United States Senate is Vice-President.</p>
  
 +
<p>The sign &ldquo;less than&rdquo; is to be so taken that</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{f} < \mathrm{m}~\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>means that every Frenchman is a man, but there are men besides Frenchmen.  Drobisch has used this sign in the same sense.  It will follow from these significations of <math>=\!</math> and <math><\!</math> that the sign <math>-\!\!\!<\!</math> (or <math>\leqq</math>, &ldquo;as small as&rdquo;) will mean &ldquo;is&rdquo;.  Thus,</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{f} ~-\!\!\!< \mathrm{m}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>means &ldquo;every Frenchman is a man&rdquo;, without saying whether there are any other men or not.  So,</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{m} ~-\!\!\!< \mathit{l}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>will mean that every mother of anything is a lover of the same thing;  although this interpretation in some degree anticipates a convention to be made further on.  These significations of <math>=\!</math> and <math><\!</math> plainly conform to the indispensable conditions.  Upon the transitive character of these relations the syllogism depends, for by virtue of it, from</p>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
{| width="100%"
 +
| width="25%" | &nbsp;
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{f} ~-\!\!\!< \mathrm{m}</math>
 +
| width="25%" | &nbsp;
 +
|-
 +
| <p>and</p>
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{m} ~-\!\!\!< \mathrm{a}</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|-
 +
| <p>we can infer that</p>
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{f} ~-\!\!\!< \mathrm{a}</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|}
 +
|-
 +
|
 
<p>that is, from every Frenchman being a man and every man being an animal, that every Frenchman is an animal.</p>
 
<p>that is, from every Frenchman being a man and every man being an animal, that every Frenchman is an animal.</p>
  
<p>But not only do the significations of '=' and '<' here adopted fulfill all absolute requirements, but they have the supererogatory virtue of being very nearly the same as the common significations.  Equality is, in fact, nothing but the identity of two numbers;  numbers that are equal are those which are predicable of the same collections, just as terms that are identical are those which are predicable of the same classes.  So, to write 5 < 7 is to say that 5 is part of 7, just as to write f < m is to say that Frenchmen are part of men.  Indeed, if f < m, then the number of Frenchmen is less than the number of men, and if v = p, then the number of Vice-Presidents is equal to the number of Presidents of the Senate;  so that the numbers may always be substituted for the terms themselves, in case no signs of operation occur in the equations or inequalities.  (Peirce, CP 3.66).</p>
+
<p>But not only do the significations of <math>=\!</math> and <math><\!</math> here adopted fulfill all absolute requirements, but they have the supererogatory virtue of being very nearly the same as the common significations.  Equality is, in fact, nothing but the identity of two numbers;  numbers that are equal are those which are predicable of the same collections, just as terms that are identical are those which are predicable of the same classes.  So, to write <math>5 < 7\!</math> is to say that <math>5\!</math> is part of <math>7\!</math>, just as to write <math>\mathrm{f} < \mathrm{m}~\!</math> is to say that Frenchmen are part of men.  Indeed, if <math>\mathrm{f} < \mathrm{m}~\!</math>, then the number of Frenchmen is less than the number of men, and if <math>\mathrm{v} = \mathrm{p}\!</math>, then the number of Vice-Presidents is equal to the number of Presidents of the Senate;  so that the numbers may always be substituted for the terms themselves, in case no signs of operation occur in the equations or inequalities.</p>
</blockquote>
 
  
The quantifier mapping from terms to their numbers that Peirce signifies by means of the square bracket notation has one of its principal uses in providing a basis for the computation of frequencies, probabilities, and all of the other statistical measures that can be constructed from these, and thus in affording what may be called a "principle of correspondence" between probability theory and its limiting case in the forms of logic.
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.66).</p>
 +
|}
  
This brings us once again to the relativity of contingency and necessity, as one way of approaching necessity is through the avenue of probability, describing necessity as a probability of 1, but the whole apparatus of probability theory only figures in if it is cast against the backdrop of probability space axioms, the reference class of distributions, and the sample space that we cannot help but to abdeuce upon the scene of observations.  Aye, there's the snake eyes.  And with them we can see that there is always an irreducible quantum of facticity to all our necessities.  More plainly spoken, it takes a fairly complex conceptual infrastructure just to begin speaking of probabilities, and this setting can only be set up by means of abductive, fallible, hypothetical, and inherently risky mental acts.
+
The quantifier mapping from terms to their numbers that Peirce signifies by means of the square bracket notation <math>[t]\!</math> has one of its principal uses in providing a basis for the computation of frequencies, probabilities, and all of the other statistical measures that can be constructed from these, and thus in affording what may be called a ''principle of correspondence'' between probability theory and its limiting case in the forms of logic.
  
Pragmatic thinking is the logic of abduction, which is just another way of saying that it addresses the question:  "What may be hoped?" We have to face the possibility that it may be just as impossible to speak of "absolute identity" with any hope of making practical philosophical sense as it is to speak of "absolute simultaneity" with any hope of making operational physical sense.
+
This brings us once again to the relativity of contingency and necessity, as one way of approaching necessity is through the avenue of probability, describing necessity as a probability of 1, but the whole apparatus of probability theory only figures in if it is cast against the backdrop of probability space axioms, the reference class of distributions, and the sample space that we cannot help but to abduce upon the scene of observations.  Aye, there's the snake eyes.  And with them we can see that there is always an irreducible quantum of facticity to all our necessities.  More plainly spoken, it takes a fairly complex conceptual infrastructure just to begin speaking of probabilities, and this setting can only be set up by means of abductive, fallible, hypothetical, and inherently risky mental acts.
 +
 
 +
Pragmatic thinking is the logic of abduction, which is just another way of saying that it addresses the question:  &ldquo;What may be hoped?&rdquo; We have to face the possibility that it may be just as impossible to speak of &ldquo;absolute identity&rdquo; with any hope of making practical philosophical sense as it is to speak of &ldquo;absolute simultaneity&rdquo; with any hope of making operational physical sense.
  
 
==Selection 4==
 
==Selection 4==
  
<blockquote>
+
===The Signs for Addition===
<p>'''The Signs for Addition'''</p>
 
  
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 +
|
 
<p>The sign of addition is taken by Boole so that</p>
 
<p>The sign of addition is taken by Boole so that</p>
 
+
|-
<p>''x'' + ''y''</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>x + y\!</math>
 
+
|-
<p>denotes everything denoted by ''x'', and, ''besides'', everything denoted by ''y''.</p>
+
|
 +
<p>denotes everything denoted by <math>x\!</math>, and, ''besides'', everything denoted by <math>y\!</math>.</p>
  
 
<p>Thus</p>
 
<p>Thus</p>
 
+
|-
<p>''m'' + ''w''</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{m} + \mathrm{w}~\!</math>
 
+
|-
 +
|
 
<p>denotes all men, and, besides, all women.</p>
 
<p>denotes all men, and, besides, all women.</p>
  
Line 121: Line 230:
  
 
<p>For example,</p>
 
<p>For example,</p>
 
+
|-
<p>''f'' + ''u''</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{f} + \mathrm{u}\!</math>
 
+
|-
 +
|
 
<p>means all Frenchmen besides all violinists, and, therefore, considered as a logical term, implies that all French violinists are ''besides themselves''.</p>
 
<p>means all Frenchmen besides all violinists, and, therefore, considered as a logical term, implies that all French violinists are ''besides themselves''.</p>
  
 
<p>For this reason alone, in a paper which is published in the Proceedings of the Academy for March 17, 1867, I preferred to take as the regular addition of logic a non-invertible process, such that</p>
 
<p>For this reason alone, in a paper which is published in the Proceedings of the Academy for March 17, 1867, I preferred to take as the regular addition of logic a non-invertible process, such that</p>
 
+
|-
<p>''m'' +, ''b''</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{m} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{b}</math>
 
+
|-
 +
|
 
<p>stands for all men and black things, without any implication that the black things are to be taken besides the men;  and the study of the logic of relatives has supplied me with other weighty reasons for the same determination.</p>
 
<p>stands for all men and black things, without any implication that the black things are to be taken besides the men;  and the study of the logic of relatives has supplied me with other weighty reasons for the same determination.</p>
  
<p>Since the publication of that paper, I have found that Mr.&nbsp;W.&nbsp;Stanley&nbsp;Jevons, in a tract called ''Pure Logic, or the Logic of Quality'' [1864], had anticipated me in substituting the same operation for Boole's addition, although he rejects Boole's operation entirely and writes the new one with a "+" sign while withholding from it the name of addition.</p>
+
<p>Since the publication of that paper, I have found that Mr.&nbsp;W.&nbsp;Stanley&nbsp;Jevons, in a tract called ''Pure Logic, or the Logic of Quality'' [1864], had anticipated me in substituting the same operation for Boole's addition, although he rejects Boole's operation entirely and writes the new one with a &nbsp;<math>+\!</math>&nbsp; sign while withholding from it the name of addition.</p>
  
<p>It is plain that both the regular non-invertible addition and the invertible addition satisfy the absolute conditions.  But the notation has other recommendations.  The conception of 'taking together' involved in these processes is strongly analogous to that of summation, the sum of 2 and 5, for example, being the number of a collection which consists of a collection of two and a collection of five.  Any logical equation or inequality in which no operation but addition is involved may be converted into a numerical equation or inequality by substituting the numbers of the several terms for the terms themselves provided all the terms summed are mutually exclusive.</p>
+
<p>It is plain that both the regular non-invertible addition and the invertible addition satisfy the absolute conditions.  But the notation has other recommendations.  The conception of ''taking together'' involved in these processes is strongly analogous to that of summation, the sum of 2 and 5, for example, being the number of a collection which consists of a collection of two and a collection of five.  Any logical equation or inequality in which no operation but addition is involved may be converted into a numerical equation or inequality by substituting the numbers of the several terms for the terms themselves &mdash; provided all the terms summed are mutually exclusive.</p>
  
<p>Addition being taken in this sense, 'nothing' is to be denoted by 'zero', for then</p>
+
<p>Addition being taken in this sense, ''nothing'' is to be denoted by ''zero'', for then</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>x ~+\!\!,~ 0 ~=~ x</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>whatever is denoted by <math>x\!</math>;  and this is the definition of ''zero''.  This interpretation is given by Boole, and is very neat, on account of the resemblance between the ordinary conception of ''zero'' and that of nothing, and because we shall thus have</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[0] ~=~ 0.</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.67).</p>
 +
|}
  
<p>''x'' +, 0 = ''x'',</p>
+
A wealth of issues arises here that I hope to take up in depth at a later point, but for the moment I shall be able to mention only the barest sample of them in passing.
  
whatever is denoted by ''x''; and this is the definition of 'zero'This interpretation is given by Boole, and is very neat, on account of the resemblance between the ordinary conception of 'zero' and that of nothing, and because we shall thus have</p>
+
The two papers that precede this one in CP&nbsp;3 are Peirce's papers of March and September 1867 in the ''Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences'', titled &ldquo;On an Improvement in Boole's Calculus of Logic&rdquo; and &ldquo;Upon the Logic of Mathematics&rdquo;, respectivelyAmong other things, these two papers provide us with further clues about the motivating considerations that brought Peirce to introduce the &ldquo;number of a term&rdquo; function, signified here by square brackets.  I have already quoted from the &ldquo;Logic of Mathematics&rdquo; paper in a related connection.  Here are the links to those excerpts:
  
<p>[0] = 0.</p>
+
<dl style="margin-left:30px;">
 +
<dt>Limited Mark Universes
 +
<dd>[http://web.archive.org/web/20140429004255/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04349.html (1)]
 +
<dd>[http://web.archive.org/web/20140429004359/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04350.html (2)]
 +
<dd>[http://web.archive.org/web/20140429004130/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04351.html (3)]
 +
</dl>
  
(Peirce, CP 3.67).
+
In setting up a correspondence between &ldquo;letters&rdquo; and &ldquo;numbers&rdquo;, Peirce constructs a structure-preserving map from a logical domain to a numerical domain.  That he does this deliberately is evidenced by the care that he takes with the conditions under which the chosen aspects of structure are preserved, along with his recognition of the critical fact that zeroes are preserved by the mapping.
  
</blockquote>
+
Incidentally, Peirce appears to have an inkling of the problems that would later be caused by using the plus sign for inclusive disjunction, but his advice was overridden by the dialects of applied logic that developed in various communities, retarding the exchange of information among engineering, mathematical, and philosophical specialties all throughout the subsequent century.
 
 
A wealth of issues arise here that I hope to take up in depth at a later point, but for the moment I shall be able to mention only the barest sample of them in passing.
 
 
 
The two papers that precede this one in CP 3 are Peirce's papers of March and September 1867 in the 'Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences', titled "On an Improvement in Boole's Calculus of Logic" and "Upon the Logic of Mathematics", respectively.  Among other things, these two papers provide us with further clues about the motivating considerations that brought Peirce to introduce the "number of a term" function, signified here by square brackets.  I have already quoted from the "Logic of Mathematics" paper in a related connection.  Here are the links to those excerpts:
 
 
 
* [http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04350.html]
 
* [http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04351.html]
 
 
 
In setting up a correspondence between "letters" and "numbers", my sense is that Peirce is "nocking an arrow", or constructing some kind of structure-preserving map from a logical domain to a numerical domain, and this interpretation is here reinforced by the careful attention that he gives to the conditions under which precisely which aspects of structure are preserved, plus his telling recognition of the criterial fact that zeroes are preserved by the mapping.  But here's the catch, the arrow is from the qualitative domain to the quantitative domain, which is just the opposite of what I tend to expect, since I think of quantitative measures as preserving more information than qualitative measures.  To curtail the story, it is possible to sort this all out, but that is a story for another day.
 
 
 
Other than that, I just want to red flag the beginnings of another one of those "failures to communicate" that so dogged the disciplines in the 20th Century, namely, the fact that Peirce seemed to have an inkling about the problems that would be caused by using the plus sign for inclusive disjunction, but, as it happens, his advice was overridden by the usages in various different communities, rendering the exchange of information among engineering, mathematical, and philosophical specialties a minefield in place of mindfield to this very day.
 
  
 
==Selection 5==
 
==Selection 5==
  
<blockquote>
+
===The Signs for Multiplication===
<p>'''The Signs for Multiplication'''</p>
 
  
<p>I shall adopt for the conception of multiplication 'the application of a relation', in such a way that, for example, 'l'w shall denote whatever is lover of a woman.  This notation is the same as that used by Mr. De Morgan, although he apears not to have had multiplication in his mind.</p>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 
+
|
<p>'s'(m +, w) will, then, denote whatever is servant of anything of the class composed of men and women taken together.  So that:</p>
+
<p>I shall adopt for the conception of multiplication ''the application of a relation'', in such a way that, for example, <math>\mathit{l}\mathrm{w}~\!</math> shall denote whatever is lover of a woman.  This notation is the same as that used by Mr.&nbsp;De&nbsp;Morgan, although he appears not to have had multiplication in his mind.</p>
 
 
<p>'s'(m +, w)  =  's'm +, 's'w.</p>
 
 
 
<p>('l' +, 's')w will denote whatever is lover or servant to a woman, and:</p>
 
 
 
<p>('l' +, 's')w  =  'l'w +, 's'w.</p>
 
 
 
<p>('sl')w will denote whatever stands to a woman in the relation of servant of a lover, and:</p>
 
 
 
<p>('sl')w  =  's'('l'w).</p>
 
  
 +
<p><math>\mathit{s}(\mathrm{m} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{w})</math> will, then, denote whatever is servant of anything of the class composed of men and women taken together.  So that:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{s}(\mathrm{m} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{w}) ~=~ \mathit{s}\mathrm{m} ~+\!\!,~ \mathit{s}\mathrm{w}.</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p><math>(\mathit{l} ~+\!\!,~ \mathit{s})\mathrm{w}</math> will denote whatever is lover or servant to a woman, and:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>(\mathit{l} ~+\!\!,~ \mathit{s})\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{l}\mathrm{w} ~+\!\!,~ \mathit{s}\mathrm{w}.</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p><math>(\mathit{s}\mathit{l})\mathrm{w}\!</math> will denote whatever stands to a woman in the relation of servant of a lover, and:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>(\mathit{s}\mathit{l})\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{s}(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w}).</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 
<p>Thus all the absolute conditions of multiplication are satisfied.</p>
 
<p>Thus all the absolute conditions of multiplication are satisfied.</p>
  
<p>The term "identical with ---" is a unity for this multiplication.  That is to say, if we denote "identical with ---" by !1! we have:</p>
+
<p>The term &ldquo;identical with&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash;&rdquo; is a unity for this multiplication.  That is to say, if we denote &ldquo;identical with&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash;&rdquo; by <math>\mathit{1}\!</math> we have:</p>
 
+
|-
<p>'x'!1=  'x',</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>x \mathit{1} ~=~ x ~ ,</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>whatever relative term <math>x\!</math> may be. For what is a lover of something identical with anything, is the same as a lover of that thing.</p>
  
<p>whatever relative term 'x' may be.  For what is a lover of something identical with anything, is the same as a lover of that thing.  (Peirce, CP 3.68).</p>
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.68).</p>
</blockquote>
+
|}
  
Peirce in 1870 is five years down the road from the Peirce of 1865–1866 who lectured extensively on the role of sign relations in the logic of scientific inquiry, articulating their involvement in the three types of inference, and inventing the concept of "information" to explain what it is that signs convey in the process.  By this time, then, the semiotic or sign relational approach to logic is so implicit in his way of working that he does not always take the trouble to point out its distinctive features at each and every turn.  So let's take a moment to draw out a few of these characters.
+
Peirce in 1870 is five years down the road from the Peirce of 1865&ndash;1866 who lectured extensively on the role of sign relations in the logic of scientific inquiry, articulating their involvement in the three types of inference, and inventing the concept of &ldquo;information&rdquo; to explain what it is that signs convey in the process.  By this time, then, the semiotic or sign relational approach to logic is so implicit in his way of working that he does not always take the trouble to point out its distinctive features at each and every turn.  So let's take a moment to draw out a few of these characters.
  
[[Sign relation]]s, like any non-trivial brand of [[3-adic relation]]s, can become overwhelming to think about once the cardinality of the object, sign, and interpretant domains or the complexity of the relation itself ascends beyond the simplest examples.  Furthermore, most of the strategies that we would normally use to control the complexity, like neglecting one of the domains, in effect, projecting the 3-adic sign relation onto one of its 2-adic faces, or focusing on a single ordered triple of the form ‹&nbsp;''o'',&nbsp;''s'',&nbsp;''i''&nbsp;› at a time, can result in our receiving a distorted impression of the sign relation's true nature and structure.
+
[[Sign relations]], like any brand of non-trivial [[3-adic relations]], can become overwhelming to think about once the cardinality of the object, sign, and interpretant domains or the complexity of the relation itself ascends beyond the simplest examples.  Furthermore, most of the strategies that we would normally use to control the complexity, like neglecting one of the domains, in effect, projecting the 3-adic sign relation onto one of its 2-adic faces, or focusing on a single ordered triple of the form <math>(o, s, i)\!</math> at a time, can result in our receiving a distorted impression of the sign relation's true nature and structure.
  
 
I find that it helps me to draw, or at least to imagine drawing, diagrams of the following form, where I can keep tabs on what's an object, what's a sign, and what's an interpretant sign, for a selected set of sign-relational triples.
 
I find that it helps me to draw, or at least to imagine drawing, diagrams of the following form, where I can keep tabs on what's an object, what's a sign, and what's an interpretant sign, for a selected set of sign-relational triples.
  
Here is how I would picture Peirce's example of equivalent terms:  ''v'' = ''p'', where "''v''" denotes the Vice-President of the United States, and "''p''" denotes the President of the Senate of the United States.
+
Here is how I would picture Peirce's example of equivalent terms, <math>\mathrm{v} = \mathrm{p},\!</math> where <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{v} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> denotes the Vice-President of the United States, and <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{p} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> denotes the President of the Senate of the United States.
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" border="0" cellspacing="10" style="text-align:center; width:100%"
o-----------------------------o-----------------------------o
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 1.jpg]]
| Objective Framework (OF)  | Interpretive Framework (IF) |
+
|-
o-----------------------------o-----------------------------o
+
| height="20px" valign="top" | <math>\text{Figure 1}~\!</math>
|           Objects          |            Signs            |
+
|}
o-----------------------------o-----------------------------o
 
|                                                           |
 
|                                o "v"                     |
 
|                                /                          |
 
|                              /                          |
 
|                              /                            |
 
|          o ... o-----------@                            |
 
|                              \                           |
 
|                              \                          |
 
|                                \                         |
 
|                                o "p"                    |
 
|                                                          |
 
o-----------------------------o-----------------------------o
 
</pre>
 
  
Depending on whether we interpret the terms "''v''" and "''p''" as applying to persons who hold these offices at one particular time or as applying to all those persons who have held these offices over an extended period of history, their denotations may be either singular of plural, respectively.
+
Depending on whether we interpret the terms <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{v} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> and <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{p} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> as applying to persons who hold these offices at one particular time or as applying to all those persons who have held these offices over an extended period of history, their denotations may be either singular of plural, respectively.
  
As a shortcut technique for indicating general denotations or plural referents, I will use the "elliptic convention" that represents these by means of figures like "o&nbsp;o&nbsp;o" or "o&nbsp;&hellip;&nbsp;o", placed at the object ends of sign relational triads.
+
As a shortcut technique for indicating general denotations or plural referents, I will use the ''elliptic convention'' that represents these by means of figures like &ldquo;o&nbsp;o&nbsp;o&rdquo; or &ldquo;o&nbsp;&hellip;&nbsp;o&rdquo;, placed at the object ends of sign relational triads.
  
 
For a more complex example, here is how I would picture Peirce's example of an equivalence between terms that comes about by applying one of the distributive laws, for relative multiplication over absolute summation.
 
For a more complex example, here is how I would picture Peirce's example of an equivalence between terms that comes about by applying one of the distributive laws, for relative multiplication over absolute summation.
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" border="0" cellspacing="10" style="text-align:center; width:100%"
o-----------------------------o-----------------------------o
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 2.jpg]]
| Objective Framework (OF)  | Interpretive Framework (IF) |
+
|-
o-----------------------------o-----------------------------o
+
| height="20px" valign="top" | <math>\text{Figure 2}\!</math>
|           Objects          |            Signs            |
+
|}
o-----------------------------o-----------------------------o
 
|                                                           |
 
|                                o "'s'(m +, w)"           |
 
|                                /                          |
 
|                              /                          |
 
|                              /                            |
 
|          o ... o-----------@                            |
 
|                              \                           |
 
|                              \                          |
 
|                                \                         |
 
|                                o "'s'm +, 's'w"          |
 
|                                                          |
 
o-----------------------------o-----------------------------o
 
</pre>
 
  
 
==Selection 6==
 
==Selection 6==
  
<blockquote>
+
===The Signs for Multiplication (cont.)===
<p>'''The Signs for Multiplication''' (cont.)</p>
 
  
<p>A conjugative term like 'giver' naturally requires two correlates, one denoting the thing given, the other the recipient of the gift.</p>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 +
|
 +
<p>A conjugative term like ''giver'' naturally requires two correlates, one denoting the thing given, the other the recipient of the gift.</p>
  
<p>We must be able to distinguish, in our notation, the giver of ''A'' to ''B'' from the giver to ''A'' of ''B'', and, therefore, I suppose the signification of the letter equivalent to such a relative to distinguish the correlates as first, second, third, etc., so that "giver of --- to ---" and "giver to --- of ---" will be expressed by different letters.</p>
+
<p>We must be able to distinguish, in our notation, the giver of <math>\mathrm{A}\!</math> to <math>\mathrm{B}\!</math> from the giver to <math>\mathrm{A}\!</math> of <math>\mathrm{B}\!</math>, and, therefore, I suppose the signification of the letter equivalent to such a relative to distinguish the correlates as first, second, third, etc., so that &ldquo;giver of&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash; to&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash;&rdquo; and &ldquo;giver to&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash; of&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash;&rdquo; will be expressed by different letters.</p>
  
<p>Let `g` denote the latter of these conjugative terms.  Then, the correlates or multiplicands of this multiplier cannot all stand directly after it, as is usual in multiplication, but may be ranged after it in regular order, so that:</p>
+
<p>Let <math>\mathfrak{g}</math> denote the latter of these conjugative terms.  Then, the correlates or multiplicands of this multiplier cannot all stand directly after it, as is usual in multiplication, but may be ranged after it in regular order, so that:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathfrak{g}\mathit{x}\mathit{y}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>will denote a giver to <math>\mathit{x}\!</math> of <math>\mathit{y}\!</math>.</p>
  
<p>`g`xy</p>
+
<p>But according to the notation, <math>\mathit{x}\!</math> here multiplies <math>\mathit{y}\!</math>, so that if we put for <math>\mathit{x}\!</math> owner (<math>\mathit{o}\!</math>), and for <math>\mathit{y}\!</math> horse (<math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>),</p>
 
+
|-
<p>will denote a giver to ''x'' of ''y''.</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}</math>
 
+
|-
<p>But according to the notation, ''x'' here multiplies ''y'', so that if we put for ''x'' owner ('o'), and for ''y'' horse (h),</p>
+
|
 
+
<p>appears to denote the giver of a horse to an owner of a horse.  But let the individual horses be <math>\mathrm{H}, \mathrm{H}^{\prime}, \mathrm{H}^{\prime\prime}</math>, etc.</p>
<p>`g`'o'h</p>
 
 
 
<p>appears to denote the giver of a horse to an owner of a horse.  But let the individual horses be ''H'', ''H''&prime;, ''H''&Prime;, etc.</p>
 
  
 
<p>Then:</p>
 
<p>Then:</p>
 
+
|-
<p>''h'' = ''H'' +, ''H''&prime; +, ''H''&Prime; +, etc.</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{h} ~=~ \mathrm{H} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{H}^{\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{H}^{\prime\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \text{etc.}</math>
 
+
|-
<p>`g`'o'h = `g`'o'(''H'' +, ''H''&prime; +, ''H''&Prime; +, etc.)</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h} ~=~ \mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}(\mathrm{H} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{H}^{\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{H}^{\prime\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \text{etc.}) ~=~ \mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{H} ~+\!\!,~ \mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{H}^{\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{H}^{\prime\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \text{etc.}</math>
 
+
|-
<p>= `g`'o' ''H'' +, `g`'o' ''H''&prime; +, `g`'o' ''H''&Prime; +, etc.</p>
+
|
 
+
<p>Now this last member must be interpreted as a giver of a horse to the owner of ''that'' horse, and this, therefore must be the interpretation of <math>\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}</math>This is always very important. ''A term multiplied by two relatives shows that the same individual is in the two relations.''</p>
<p>Now this last member must be interpreted as a giver of a horse to the owner of 'that' horse, and this, therefore must be the interpretation of `g`'o'h.</p>
 
 
 
<p>This is always very important.</p>
 
 
 
<p>'A term multiplied by two relatives shows that the same individual is in the two relations.'</p>
 
  
 
<p>If we attempt to express the giver of a horse to a lover of a woman, and for that purpose write:</p>
 
<p>If we attempt to express the giver of a horse to a lover of a woman, and for that purpose write:</p>
 
+
|-
<p>`g`'l'wh,</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathfrak{g}\mathit{l}\mathrm{w}\mathrm{h}</math>,
 
+
|-
 +
|
 
<p>we have written giver of a woman to a lover of her, and if we add brackets, thus,</p>
 
<p>we have written giver of a woman to a lover of her, and if we add brackets, thus,</p>
 
+
|-
<p>`g`('l'w)h,</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathfrak{g}(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})\mathrm{h}</math>,
 
+
|-
 +
|
 
<p>we abandon the associative principle of multiplication.</p>
 
<p>we abandon the associative principle of multiplication.</p>
  
<p>A little reflection will show that the associative principle must in some form or other be abandoned at this point.  But while this principle is sometimes falsified, it oftener holds, and a notation must be adopted which will show of itself when it holds.  We already see that we cannot express multiplication by writing the multiplicand directly after the multiplier;  let us then affix subjacent numbers after letters to show where their correlates are to be found.  The first number shall denote how many factors must be counted from left to right to reach the first correlate, the second how many 'more' must be counted to reach the second, and so on.</p>
+
<p>A little reflection will show that the associative principle must in some form or other be abandoned at this point.  But while this principle is sometimes falsified, it oftener holds, and a notation must be adopted which will show of itself when it holds.  We already see that we cannot express multiplication by writing the multiplicand directly after the multiplier;  let us then affix subjacent numbers after letters to show where their correlates are to be found.  The first number shall denote how many factors must be counted from left to right to reach the first correlate, the second how many ''more'' must be counted to reach the second, and so on.</p>
  
 
<p>Then, the giver of a horse to a lover of a woman may be written:</p>
 
<p>Then, the giver of a horse to a lover of a woman may be written:</p>
 
+
|-
<p>`g`<sub>12</sub>'l'<sub>1</sub>''wh'' = `g`<sub>11</sub>'l'<sub>2</sub>''hw'' = `g`<sub>2(–1)</sub>h'l'<sub>1</sub>''w''.</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathfrak{g}_{12} \mathit{l}_1 \mathrm{w} \mathrm{h} ~=~ \mathfrak{g}_{11} \mathit{l}_2 \mathrm{h} \mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathfrak{g}_{2(-1)} \mathrm{h} \mathit{l}_1 \mathrm{w}</math>.
 
+
|-
 +
|
 
<p>Of course a negative number indicates that the former correlate follows the latter by the corresponding positive number.</p>
 
<p>Of course a negative number indicates that the former correlate follows the latter by the corresponding positive number.</p>
  
<p>A subjacent 'zero' makes the term itself the correlate.</p>
+
<p>A subjacent ''zero'' makes the term itself the correlate.</p>
  
 
<p>Thus,</p>
 
<p>Thus,</p>
 
+
|-
<p>'l'<sub>0</sub></p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{l}_0\!</math>
 
+
|-
<p>denotes the lover of 'that' lover or the lover of himself, just as `g`'o'h denotes that the horse is given to the owner of itself, for to make a term doubly a correlate is, by the distributive principle, to make each individual doubly a correlate, so that:</p>
+
|
 
+
<p>denotes the lover of ''that'' lover or the lover of himself, just as <math>\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}</math> denotes that the horse is given to the owner of itself, for to make a term doubly a correlate is, by the distributive principle, to make each individual doubly a correlate, so that:</p>
<p>'l'<sub>0</sub> = L<sub>0</sub> +, L<sub>0</sub>&prime; +, L<sub>0</sub>&Prime; +, etc.</p>
+
|-
 
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{l}_0 ~=~ \mathit{L}_0 ~+\!\!,~ \mathit{L}_0^{\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathit{L}_0^{\prime\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \text{etc.}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 
<p>A subjacent sign of infinity may indicate that the correlate is indeterminate, so that:</p>
 
<p>A subjacent sign of infinity may indicate that the correlate is indeterminate, so that:</p>
 
+
|-
<p>'l'<sub>&infin;</sub></p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{l}_\infty</math>
 
+
|-
 +
|
 
<p>will denote a lover of something.  We shall have some confirmation of this presently.</p>
 
<p>will denote a lover of something.  We shall have some confirmation of this presently.</p>
  
<p>If the last subjacent number is a 'one' it may be omitted.  Thus we shall have:</p>
+
<p>If the last subjacent number is a ''one'' it may be omitted.  Thus we shall have:</p>
 
+
|-
<p>'l'<sub>1</sub> = 'l',</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{l}_1 ~=~ \mathit{l}</math>,
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathfrak{g}_{11} ~=~ \mathfrak{g}_1 ~=~ \mathfrak{g}</math>.
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>This enables us to retain our former expressions <math>\mathit{l}\mathrm{w}~\!</math>, <math>\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}</math>, etc.</p>
  
<p>`g`<sub>11</sub> = `g`<sub>1</sub> = `g`.</p>
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.69&ndash;70).</p>
 +
|}
  
<p>This enables us to retain our former expressions 'l'w, `g`'o'h, etc.</p>
+
===Comment : Sets as Logical Sums===
  
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.69–70).</p>
+
Peirce's way of representing sets as logical sums may seem archaic, but it is quite often used, and is actually the tool of choice in many branches of algebra, combinatorics, computing, and statistics to this very day.
</blockquote>
 
  
Peirce's way of representing sets as sums may seem archaic, but it is quite often used, and is actually the tool of choice in many branches of algebra, combinatorics, computing, and statistics to this very day.
+
Peirce's application to logic is fairly novel, and the degree of his elaboration of the logic of relative terms is certainly original with him, but this particular genre of representation, commonly going under the handle of ''generating functions'', goes way back, well before anyone thought to stick a flag in set theory as a separate territory or to try to fence off our native possessions of it with expressly decreed axioms.  And back in the days when a computer was just a person who computed, before we had the sorts of ''electronic register machines'' that we take so much for granted today, mathematicians were constantly using generating functions as a rough and ready type of addressable memory to sort, store, and keep track of their accounts of a wide variety of formal objects of thought.
 
 
Peirce's application to logic is fairly novel, and the degree of his elaboration of the logic of relative terms is certainly original with him, but this particular genre of representation, commonly going under the handle of "generating functions", goes way back, well before anyone thought to stick a flag in set theory as a separate territory or to try to fence off our native possessions of it with expressly decreed axioms.  And back in the days when computers were people, before we had the sorts of "electronic register machines" that we take so much for granted today, mathematicians were constantly using generating functions as a rough and ready type of addressable memory to sort, store, and keep track of their accounts of a wide variety of formal objects of thought.
 
  
 
Let us look at a few simple examples of generating functions, much as I encountered them during my own first adventures in the Fair Land Of Combinatoria.
 
Let us look at a few simple examples of generating functions, much as I encountered them during my own first adventures in the Fair Land Of Combinatoria.
  
Suppose that we are given a set of three elements, say, {''a'',&nbsp;''b'',&nbsp;''c''}, and we are asked to find all the ways of choosing a subset from this collection.
+
Suppose that we are given a set of three elements, say, <math>\{ a, b, c \},\!</math> and we are asked to find all the ways of choosing a subset from this collection.
  
 
We can represent this problem setup as the problem of computing the following product:
 
We can represent this problem setup as the problem of computing the following product:
  
: (1 + ''a'')(1 + ''b'')(1 + ''c'').
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>(1 + a)(1 + b)(1 + c).\!</math>
 +
|}
  
The factor (1&nbsp;+&nbsp;''a'') represents the option that we have, in choosing a subset of {''a'',&nbsp;''b'',&nbsp;''c''}, to leave the ''a'' out (signified by the "1"), or else to include it (signified by the "''a''"), and likewise for the other elements ''b'' and ''c'' in their turns.
+
The factor <math>(1 + a)\!</math> represents the option that we have, in choosing a subset of <math>\{ a, b, c \},\!</math> to leave the element <math>a\!</math> out (signified by the <math>1\!</math>), or else to include it (signified by the <math>a\!</math>), and likewise for the other elements <math>b\!</math> and <math>c\!</math> in their turns.
  
 
Probably on account of all those years I flippered away playing the oldtime pinball machines, I tend to imagine a product like this being displayed in a vertical array:
 
Probably on account of all those years I flippered away playing the oldtime pinball machines, I tend to imagine a product like this being displayed in a vertical array:
  
: (1 + ''a'')
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
: (1 + ''b'')
+
|
: (1 + ''c'')
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
(1 ~+~ a)
 +
\\
 +
(1 ~+~ b)
 +
\\
 +
(1 ~+~ c)
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|}
  
I picture this as a playboard with six "bumpers", the ball chuting down the board in such a career that it strikes exactly one of the two bumpers on each and every one of the three levels.
+
I picture this as a playboard with six bumpers, the ball chuting down the board in such a career that it strikes exactly one of the two bumpers on each and every one of the three levels.
  
<pre>
+
So a trajectory of the ball where it hits the <math>a\!</math> bumper on the 1st level, hits the <math>1\!</math> bumper on the 2nd level, hits the <math>c\!</math> bumper on the 3rd level, and then exits the board, represents a single term in the desired product and corresponds to the subset <math>\{ a, c \}.\!</math>
So a trajectory of the ball where it
 
hits the "a" bumper on the 1st level,
 
hits the "1" bumper on the 2nd level,
 
hits the "c" bumper on the 3rd level,
 
and then exits the board, represents
 
a single term in the desired product
 
and corresponds to the subset {a, c}.
 
</pre>
 
  
Multiplying out (1 + ''a'')(1 + ''b'')(1 + ''c''), one obtains:
+
Multiplying out the product <math>(1 + a)(1 + b)(1 + c),\!</math> one obtains:
  
: 1 + ''a'' + ''b'' + ''c'' + ''ab'' + ''ac'' + ''bc'' + ''abc''.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{15}{c}}
 +
1 & + & a & + & b & + & c & + & ab & + & ac & + & bc & + & abc.
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
And this informs us that the subsets of choice are:
 
And this informs us that the subsets of choice are:
  
: {}, {''a''}, {''b''}, {''c''}, {''a'', ''b''}, {''a'', ''c''}, {''b'', ''c''}, {''a'', ''b'', ''c''}.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\varnothing, & \{ a \}, & \{ b \}, & \{ c \}, & \{ a, b \}, & \{ a, c \}, & \{ b, c \}, & \{ a, b, c \}.
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
==Selection 7==
 
==Selection 7==
  
<blockquote>
+
===The Signs for Multiplication (cont.)===
<p>'''The Signs for Multiplication''' (cont.)</p>
 
 
 
<p>The associative principle does not hold in this counting of factors.  Because it does not hold, these subjacent numbers are frequently inconvenient in practice, and I therefore use also another mode of showing where the correlate of a term is to be found.  This is by means of the marks of reference, † ‡ || § ¶, which are placed subjacent to the relative term and before and above the correlate.  Thus, giver of a horse to a lover of a woman may be written:</p>
 
 
 
:<p>`g`_†‡ †'l'_|| ||w ‡h.</p>
 
  
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 +
|
 +
<p>The associative principle does not hold in this counting of factors.  Because it does not hold, these subjacent numbers are frequently inconvenient in practice, and I therefore use also another mode of showing where the correlate of a term is to be found.  This is by means of the marks of reference, <math>\dagger ~ \ddagger ~ \parallel ~ \S ~ \P</math>, which are placed subjacent to the relative term and before and above the correlate.  Thus, giver of a horse to a lover of a woman may be written:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathfrak{g}_{\dagger\ddagger} \, ^\dagger\mathit{l}_\parallel \, ^\parallel\mathrm{w} \, ^\ddagger\mathrm{h}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 
<p>The asterisk I use exclusively to refer to the last correlate of the last relative of the algebraic term.</p>
 
<p>The asterisk I use exclusively to refer to the last correlate of the last relative of the algebraic term.</p>
  
<p>Now, considering the order of multiplication to be: a term, a correlate of it, a correlate of that correlate, etc. there is no violation of the associative principle.  The only violations of it in this mode of notation are that in thus passing from relative to correlate, we skip about among the factors in an irregular manner, and that we cannot substitute in such an expression as `g`'o'h a single letter for 'o'h.</p>
+
<p>Now, considering the order of multiplication to be: &mdash; a term, a correlate of it, a correlate of that correlate, etc. &mdash; there is no violation of the associative principle.  The only violations of it in this mode of notation are that in thus passing from relative to correlate, we skip about among the factors in an irregular manner, and that we cannot substitute in such an expression as <math>\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}</math> a single letter for <math>\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}.\!</math></p>
  
<p>I would suggest that such a notation may be found useful in treating other cases of non-associative multiplication.  By comparing this with what was said above [in CP 3.55] concerning functional multiplication, it appears that multiplication by a conjugative term is functional, and that the letter denoting such a term is a symbol of operation.  I am therefore using two alphabets, the Greek and Kennerly, where only one was necessary.  But it is convenient to use both.  (Peirce, CP 3.71–72).</p>
+
<p>I would suggest that such a notation may be found useful in treating other cases of non-associative multiplication.  By comparing this with what was said above [in CP 3.55] concerning functional multiplication, it appears that multiplication by a conjugative term is functional, and that the letter denoting such a term is a symbol of operation.  I am therefore using two alphabets, the Greek and Kennerly, where only one was necessary.  But it is convenient to use both.</p>
</blockquote>
 
  
NB. On account of the fact that various listservers balk at Peirce's "marks of reference" I will make the following substitutions in Peirce's text:
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.71&ndash;72).</p>
 +
|}
  
: @  = dagger symbol
+
===Comment : Proto-Graphical Syntax===
: #  = double dagger
 
: || = parallel sign
 
: $  = section symbol
 
: %  = paragraph mark
 
  
 
It is clear from our last excerpt that Peirce is already on the verge of a graphical syntax for the logic of relatives.  Indeed, it seems likely that he had already reached this point in his own thinking.
 
It is clear from our last excerpt that Peirce is already on the verge of a graphical syntax for the logic of relatives.  Indeed, it seems likely that he had already reached this point in his own thinking.
  
For instance, it seems quite impossible to read his last variation on the theme of a "giver of a horse to a lover of a woman" without drawing lines of identity to connect up the corresponding marks of reference, like this:
+
For instance, it seems quite impossible to read his last variation on the theme of a &ldquo;giver of a horse to a lover of a woman&rdquo; without drawing lines of identity to connect up the corresponding marks of reference, like this:
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o---------------------------------------o
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 3.jpg]] || (3)
|                                      |
+
|}
|            @        ||                |
 
|          / \      /  \              |
 
|          o  o    o    o              |
 
|      `g`_@#  @'l'_||  ||w  #h        |
 
|           o                o          |
 
|           \______________/          |
 
|                   #                  |
 
|                                      |
 
o---------------------------------------o
 
Giver of a Horse to a Lover of a Woman
 
</pre>
 
  
 
==Selection 8==
 
==Selection 8==
  
<blockquote>
+
===The Signs for Multiplication (cont.)===
<p>'''The Signs for Multiplication''' (cont.)</p>
 
  
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 +
|
 
<p>Thus far, we have considered the multiplication of relative terms only.  Since our conception of multiplication is the application of a relation, we can only multiply absolute terms by considering them as relatives.</p>
 
<p>Thus far, we have considered the multiplication of relative terms only.  Since our conception of multiplication is the application of a relation, we can only multiply absolute terms by considering them as relatives.</p>
  
<p>Now the absolute term "man" is really exactly equivalent to the relative term "man that is ---", and so with any other.  I shall write a comma after any absolute term to show that it is so regarded as a relative term.</p>
+
<p>Now the absolute term &ldquo;man&rdquo; is really exactly equivalent to the relative term &ldquo;man that is&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash;&rdquo;, and so with any other.  I shall write a comma after any absolute term to show that it is so regarded as a relative term.</p>
 
 
<p>Then:</p>
 
 
 
: <p>"man that is black"</p>
 
 
 
<p>will be written</p>
 
 
 
: <p>m,b.</p>
 
  
 +
<p>Then &ldquo;man that is black&rdquo; will be written:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{m},\!\mathrm{b}\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 
<p>But not only may any absolute term be thus regarded as a relative term, but any relative term may in the same way be regarded as a relative with one correlate more.  It is convenient to take this additional correlate as the first one.</p>
 
<p>But not only may any absolute term be thus regarded as a relative term, but any relative term may in the same way be regarded as a relative with one correlate more.  It is convenient to take this additional correlate as the first one.</p>
  
 
<p>Then:</p>
 
<p>Then:</p>
 
+
|-
: <p>'l','s'w</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w}</math>
 
+
|-
 +
|
 
<p>will denote a lover of a woman that is a servant of that woman.</p>
 
<p>will denote a lover of a woman that is a servant of that woman.</p>
  
<p>The comma here after 'l' should not be considered as altering at all the meaning of 'l', but as only a subjacent sign, serving to alter the arrangement of the correlates.</p>
+
<p>The comma here after <math>\mathit{l}\!</math> should not be considered as altering at all the meaning of <math>\mathit{l}\!</math>, but as only a subjacent sign, serving to alter the arrangement of the correlates.</p>
  
 
<p>In point of fact, since a comma may be added in this way to any relative term, it may be added to one of these very relatives formed by a comma, and thus by the addition of two commas an absolute term becomes a relative of two correlates.</p>
 
<p>In point of fact, since a comma may be added in this way to any relative term, it may be added to one of these very relatives formed by a comma, and thus by the addition of two commas an absolute term becomes a relative of two correlates.</p>
  
 
<p>So:</p>
 
<p>So:</p>
 
+
|-
: <p>m,,b,r</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{m},\!,\!\mathrm{b},\!\mathrm{r}</math>
 
+
|-
 +
|
 
<p>interpreted like</p>
 
<p>interpreted like</p>
 
+
|-
: <p>`g`'o'h</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}</math>
 
+
|-
 +
|
 
<p>means a man that is a rich individual and is a black that is that rich individual.</p>
 
<p>means a man that is a rich individual and is a black that is that rich individual.</p>
  
 
<p>But this has no other meaning than:</p>
 
<p>But this has no other meaning than:</p>
 
+
|-
: <p>m,b,r</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{m},\!\mathrm{b},\!\mathrm{r}</math>
 
+
|-
 +
|
 
<p>or a man that is a black that is rich.</p>
 
<p>or a man that is a black that is rich.</p>
  
 
<p>Thus we see that, after one comma is added, the addition of another does not change the meaning at all, so that whatever has one comma after it must be regarded as having an infinite number.</p>
 
<p>Thus we see that, after one comma is added, the addition of another does not change the meaning at all, so that whatever has one comma after it must be regarded as having an infinite number.</p>
  
<p>If, therefore, 'l',,'s'w is not the same as 'l','s'w (as it plainly is not, because the latter means a lover and servant of a woman, and the former a lover of and servant of and same as a woman), this is simply because the writing of the comma alters the arrangement of the correlates.</p>
+
<p>If, therefore, <math>\mathit{l},\!,\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w}</math> is not the same as <math>\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w}</math> (as it plainly is not, because the latter means a lover and servant of a woman, and the former a lover of and servant of and same as a woman), this is simply because the writing of the comma alters the arrangement of the correlates.</p>
  
<p>And if we are to suppose that absolute terms are multipliers at all (as mathematical generality demands that we should}, we must regard every term as being a relative requiring an infinite number of correlates to its virtual infinite series "that is --- and is --- and is --- etc."</p>
+
<p>And if we are to suppose that absolute terms are multipliers at all (as mathematical generality demands that we should}, we must regard every term as being a relative requiring an infinite number of correlates to its virtual infinite series &ldquo;that is&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash; and is&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash; and is&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash; etc.&rdquo;</p>
  
 
<p>Now a relative formed by a comma of course receives its subjacent numbers like any relative, but the question is, What are to be the implied subjacent numbers for these implied correlates?</p>
 
<p>Now a relative formed by a comma of course receives its subjacent numbers like any relative, but the question is, What are to be the implied subjacent numbers for these implied correlates?</p>
  
<p>Any term may be regarded as having an infinite number of factors, those at the end being 'ones', thus:</p>
+
<p>Any term may be regarded as having an infinite number of factors, those at the end being ''ones'', thus:</p>
 
+
|-
: <p>'l','s'w = 'l','s'w,!1!,!1!,!1!,!1!,!1!,!1!,!1!, etc.</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathit{w},\!\mathit{1},\!\mathit{1},\!\mathit{1},\!\mathit{1},\!\mathit{1},\!\mathit{1},\!\mathit{1}, ~\text{etc.}</math>
 
+
|-
 +
|
 
<p>A subjacent number may therefore be as great as we please.</p>
 
<p>A subjacent number may therefore be as great as we please.</p>
  
<p>But all these 'ones' denote the same identical individual denoted by w;  what then can be the subjacent numbers to be applied to 's', for instance, on account of its infinite "that is"'s?  What numbers can separate it from being identical with w?  There are only two.  The first is 'zero', which plainly neutralizes a comma completely, since</p>
+
<p>But all these ''ones'' denote the same identical individual denoted by <math>\mathrm{w}\!</math>;  what then can be the subjacent numbers to be applied to <math>\mathit{s}\!</math>, for instance, on account of its infinite &ldquo;''that is''&rdquo;'s?  What numbers can separate it from being identical with <math>\mathrm{w}\!</math>?  There are only two.  The first is ''zero'', which plainly neutralizes a comma completely, since</p>
 
+
|-
: <p>'s',_0 w = 's'w</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{s},_0\!\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{s}\mathrm{w}</math>
 
+
|-
<p>and the other is infinity;  for as 1<sup>&infin;</sup> is indeterminate in ordinary algbra, so it will be shown hereafter to be here, so that to remove the correlate by the product of an infinite series of 'ones' is to leave it indeterminate.</p>
+
|
 +
<p>and the other is infinity;  for as <math>1^\infty</math> is indeterminate in ordinary algbra, so it will be shown hereafter to be here, so that to remove the correlate by the product of an infinite series of ''ones'' is to leave it indeterminate.</p>
  
 
<p>Accordingly,</p>
 
<p>Accordingly,</p>
 
+
|-
: <p>m,<sub>&infin;</sub></p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{m},_\infty</math>
 
+
|-
<p>should be regarded as expressing 'some' man.</p>
+
|
 +
<p>should be regarded as expressing ''some'' man.</p>
  
 
<p>Any term, then, is properly to be regarded as having an infinite number of commas, all or some of which are neutralized by zeros.</p>
 
<p>Any term, then, is properly to be regarded as having an infinite number of commas, all or some of which are neutralized by zeros.</p>
  
<p>"Something" may then be expressed by:</p>
+
<p>&ldquo;Something&rdquo; may then be expressed by:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{1}_\infty\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>I shall for brevity frequently express this by an antique figure one <math>(\mathfrak{1}).</math></p>
  
: <p>!1!<sub>&infin;</sub>.</p>
+
<p>&ldquo;Anything&rdquo; by:</p>
 
+
|-
<p>I shall for brevity frequently express this by an antique figure one (`1`).</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{1}_0\!</math>
 
+
|-
<p>"Anything" by:</p>
+
|
 
+
<p>I shall often also write a straight <math>1\!</math> for ''anything''.</p>
: <p>!1!<sub>0</sub>.</p>
 
 
 
<p>I shall often also write a straight 1 for 'anything'.</p>
 
  
 
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.73).</p>
 
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.73).</p>
</blockquote>
+
|}
  
 
===Commentary Note 8.1===
 
===Commentary Note 8.1===
  
To my way of thinking, CP 3.73 is one of the most remarkable passages in the history of logic.  In this first pass over its deeper contents I won't be able to accord it much more than a superficial dusting off.
+
To my way of thinking, CP&nbsp;3.73 is one of the most remarkable passages in the history of logic.  In this first pass over its deeper contents I won't be able to accord it much more than a superficial dusting off.
  
As always, it is probably best to begin with a concrete example.  So let us initiate a discourse, whose universe ''X'' may remind us a little of the cast of characters in Shakespeare's ''Othello''.
+
Let us imagine a concrete example that will serve in developing the uses of Peirce's notationEntertain a discourse whose universe <math>X\!</math> will remind us a little of the cast of characters in Shakespeare's ''Othello''.
  
: ''X'' = {Bianca, Cassio, Clown, Desdemona, Emilia, Iago, Othello}.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>X ~=~ \{ \mathrm{Bianca}, \mathrm{Cassio}, \mathrm{Clown}, \mathrm{Desdemona}, \mathrm{Emilia}, \mathrm{Iago}, \mathrm{Othello} \}.</math>
 +
|}
  
The universe ''X'' is "that class of individuals ''about'' which alone the whole discourse is understood to run" but its marking out for special recognition as a universe of discourse in no way rules out the possibility that "discourse may run upon something which is not a subjective part of the universe;  for instance, upon the qualities or collections of the individuals it contains" (CP 3.65).
+
The universe <math>X\!</math> is &ldquo;that class of individuals ''about'' which alone the whole discourse is understood to run&rdquo; but its marking out for special recognition as a universe of discourse in no way rules out the possibility that &ldquo;discourse may run upon something which is not a subjective part of the universe;  for instance, upon the qualities or collections of the individuals it contains&rdquo; (CP&nbsp;3.65).
  
In order to provide ourselves with the convenience of abbreviated terms, while staying a bit closer to Peirce's conventions about capitalization, let us rename the universe "''u''", the Clown "Jeste", and then rewrite the above description of the universe of discourse in the following fashion:
+
In order to provide ourselves with the convenience of abbreviated terms, while preserving Peirce's conventions about capitalization, we may use the alternate names <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{u}^{\prime\prime}</math> for the universe <math>X\!</math> and <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{Jeste}^{\prime\prime}</math> for the character <math>\mathrm{Clown}.~\!</math>  This permits the above description of the universe of discourse to be rewritten in the following fashion:
  
: ''u'' = {B, C, D, E, I, J, O}.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>\mathrm{u} ~=~ \{ \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C}, \mathrm{D}, \mathrm{E}, \mathrm{I}, \mathrm{J}, \mathrm{O} \}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
This specification of the universe of discourse could be summed up in Peirce's notation by the following equation:
 
This specification of the universe of discourse could be summed up in Peirce's notation by the following equation:
  
: 1 = B +, C +, D +, E +, I +, J +, O.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{15}{c}}
 +
\mathbf{1}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
Within this discussion, then, the "individual terms" are "B", "C", "D", "E", "I", "J", "O", each of which denotes in a singular fashion the corresponding individual in ''X''.
+
Within this discussion, then, the ''individual terms'' are as follows:
  
As "general terms" of this discussion, we might begin with the following set:
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{B}^{\prime\prime}, &
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{C}^{\prime\prime}, &
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{D}^{\prime\prime}, &
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{E}^{\prime\prime}, &
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{I}^{\prime\prime}, &
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{J}^{\prime\prime}, &
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{O}^{\prime\prime}
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|}
  
: "b" = "black"
+
Each of these terms denotes in a singular fashion the corresponding individual in <math>X.\!</math>
  
: "m" = "man"
+
By way of ''general terms'' in this discussion, we may begin with the following set:
  
: "w" = "woman"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{ccl}
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{b}^{\prime\prime}
 +
& = &
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{black}^{\prime\prime}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{m}^{\prime\prime}
 +
& = &
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{man}^{\prime\prime}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{w}^{\prime\prime}
 +
& = &
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{woman}^{\prime\prime}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
In Peirce's notation, the denotation of a general term can be expressed by means of an equation between terms:
+
The denotation of a general term may be given by means of an equation between terms:
  
: b = O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
+
|
: m = C +, I +, J +, O
+
<math>\begin{array}{*{15}{c}}
 
+
\mathrm{b}
: w = B +, D +, E
+
& =     & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{m}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{w}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
===Commentary Note 8.2===
 
===Commentary Note 8.2===
  
I will continue with my commentary on CP 3.73, developing the Othello example as a way of illustrating its concepts.
+
I continue with my commentary on CP&nbsp;3.73, developing the ''Othello'' example as a way of illustrating Peirce's concepts.
  
 
In the development of the story so far, we have a universe of discourse that can be characterized by means of the following system of equations:
 
In the development of the story so far, we have a universe of discourse that can be characterized by means of the following system of equations:
  
: 1 = B +, C +, D +, E +, I +, J +, O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{15}{c}}
 +
\mathbf{1}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{b}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{m}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{w}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
: b =  O
+
This much provides a basis for collection of absolute terms that I plan to use in this example. Let us now consider how we might represent a sufficiently exemplary collection of relative terms.
  
: m  =  C +, I +, J +, O
+
Consider the genesis of relative terms, for example:
  
: w  = B +, D +, E
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{l}
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{lover of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{betrayer to}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, \text{of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{winner over of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, \text{to}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, \text{from}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
This much provides a basis for collection of absolute terms that I plan to use in this example.  Let us now consider how we might represent a sufficiently exemplary collection of relative terms.
+
We may regard these fill-in-the-blank forms as being derived by a kind of ''rhematic abstraction'' from the corresponding instances of absolute terms.
 
 
If we consider the genesis of relative terms, for example, "lover of ---", "betrayer to --- of ---", or "winner over of --- to --- from ---", we may regard these fill-in-the-blank forms as being derived by way of a kind of "rhematic abstraction" from the corresponding instances of absolute terms.
 
  
 
In other words:
 
In other words:
  
# The relative term "lover of ---" can be constructed by abstracting the absolute term "Emilia" from the absolute term "lover of Emilia".  Since Iago is a lover of Emilia, the relate-correlate pair denoted by "Iago:Emilia" is a summand of the relative term "lover of ---".
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
# The relative term "betrayer to --- of ---" can be constructed by abstracting the absolute terms "Othello" and "Desdemona" from the absolute term "betrayer to Othello of Desdemona".  In as much as Iago is a betrayer to Othello of Desdemona, the relate-correlate-correlate triple denoted by "I:O:D" belongs to the relative term "betrayer to --- of ---".
+
|
# The relative term "winner over of --- to --- from ---" can be constructed by abstracting the absolute terms "Othello", "Iago", and "Cassio" from the absolute term "winner over of Othello to Iago from Cassio".  Since Iago is a winner over of Othello to Iago from Cassio, the elementary relative term "I:O:I:C" belongs to the relative term "winner over of --- to --- from ---".
+
<p>The relative term <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{lover of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}</math></p>
  
===Commentary Note 8.3===
+
<p>can be reached by removing the absolute term <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{Emilia}\, ^{\prime\prime}</math></p>
  
Speaking very strictly, we need to be careful to distinguish a "relation" from a "relative term".
+
<p>from the absolute term <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{lover of Emilia}\, ^{\prime\prime}.</math></p>
# The relation is an ''object'' of thought that may be regarded "in extension" as a set of ordered tuples that are known as its "elementary relations".
 
# The relative term is a ''sign'' that denotes certain objects, called its "relates", as these are determined in relation to certain other objects, called its "correlates".  Under most circumstances, one may also regard the relative term as denoting the corresponding relation.
 
  
Returning to the Othello example, let us take up the 2-adic relatives "lover of ---" and "servant of ---".
+
<p><math>\text{Iago}</math> is a lover of <math>\text{Emilia},</math> so the relate-correlate pair <math>\mathrm{I}:\mathrm{E}</math></p>
  
Ignoring the many splendored nuances appurtenant to the idea of love, we may regard the relative term 'l' for "lover of ---" to be given by the following equation:
+
<p>lies in the 2-adic relation associated with the relative term <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{lover of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}.</math></p>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>The relative term <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{betrayer to}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, \text{of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}</math></p>
  
: 'l' = B:C +, C:B +, D:O +, E:I +, I:E +, O:D.
+
<p>can be reached by removing the absolute terms <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{Othello}\, ^{\prime\prime}</math> and <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{Desdemona}\, ^{\prime\prime}</math></p>
  
If for no better reason than to make the example more interesting, let us put aside all distinctions of rank and fealty, collapsing the motley crews of attendant, servant, subordinate, and so on, under the heading of a single service, denoted by the relative term 's' for "servant of ---". The terms of this service are:
+
<p>from the absolute term <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{betrayer to Othello of Desdemona}\, ^{\prime\prime}.</math></p>
  
: 's'  =  C:O +, E:D +, I:O +, J:D +, J:O.
+
<p><math>\text{Iago}</math> is a betrayer to <math>\text{Othello}</math> of <math>\text{Desdemona},</math> so the relate-correlate-correlate triple <math>\mathrm{I}:\mathrm{O}:\mathrm{D}</math></p>
  
The term I:C may also be implied, but, since it is so hotly arguable, I will leave it out of the toll.
+
<p>lies in the 3-adic relation assciated with the relative term <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{betrayer to}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, \text{of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}.\!</math></p>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>The relative term <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{winner over of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, \text{to}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, \text{from}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}</math></p>
  
One more thing that we need to be duly wary about:  There are many different conventions in the field as to the ordering of terms in their applications, and it happens that different conventions will be more convenient under different circumstances, so there does not appear to be much of a chance that any one of them can be canonized once and for all.
+
<p>can be reached by removing the absolute terms <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{Othello}\, ^{\prime\prime},</math> <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{Iago}\, ^{\prime\prime},</math> and <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{Cassio}\, ^{\prime\prime}</math></p>
  
In the current reading, we are applying relative terms from right to left, and so our conception of relative multiplication, or relational composition, will need to be adjusted accordingly.
+
<p>from the absolute term <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{winner over of Othello to Iago from Cassio}\, ^{\prime\prime}.</math></p>
  
===Commentary Note 8.4===
+
<p><math>\text{Iago}</math> is a winner over of <math>\text{Othello}</math> to <math>\text{Iago}</math> from <math>\text{Cassio},\!</math> so the elementary relative term <math>\mathrm{I}:\mathrm{O}:\mathrm{I}:\mathrm{C}</math></p>
  
To familiarize ourselves with the forms of calculation that are available in Peirce's notation, let us compute a few of the simplest products that we find at hand in the Othello case.
+
<p>lies in the 4-adic relation associated with the relative term <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{winner over of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, \text{to}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, \text{from}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}.</math></p>
 +
|}
  
Here are the absolute terms:
+
===Commentary Note 8.3===
  
: 1 = B +, C +, D +, E +, I +, J +, O
+
Speaking very strictly, we need to be careful to distinguish a ''relation'' from a ''relative term''.
  
: b = O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<p>The relation is an ''object'' of thought that may be regarded ''in extension'' as a set of ordered tuples that are known as its ''elementary relations''.</p>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>The relative term is a ''sign'' that denotes certain objects, called its ''relates'', as these are determined in relation to certain other objects, called its ''correlates''.  Under most circumstances, one may also regard the relative term as denoting the corresponding relation.</p>
 +
|}
  
: m = C +, I +, J +, O
+
Returning to the Othello example, let us take up the 2-adic relatives <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{lover of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}</math> and <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{servant of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}.</math>
  
: w = B +, D +, E
+
Ignoring the many splendored nuances appurtenant to the idea of love, we may regard the relative term <math>\mathit{l}\!</math> for <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{lover of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}</math> to be given by the following equation:
  
Here are the 2-adic relative terms:
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{13}{c}}
 +
\mathit{l}
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{B}:\mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{C}:\mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{D}:\mathrm{O}
 +
& +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{E}:\mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{I}:\mathrm{E}
 +
& +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{O}:\mathrm{D}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
: 'l'  =  B:C +, C:B +, D:O +, E:I +, I:E +, O:D
+
If for no better reason than to make the example more interesting, let us put aside all distinctions of rank and fealty, collapsing the motley crews of attendant, servant, subordinate, and so on, under the heading of a single service, denoted by the relative term <math>\mathit{s}\!</math> for <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{servant of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, ^{\prime\prime}.</math>  The terms of this service are:
  
: 's= C:O +, E:D +, I:O +, J:D +, J:O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{11}{c}}
 +
\mathit{s}
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{C}:\mathrm{O}
 +
& +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{E}:\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{I}:\mathrm{O}
 +
& +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{J}:\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{J}:\mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
Here are a few of the simplest products among these terms:
+
The term <math>\mathrm{I}:\mathrm{C}\!</math> may also be implied, but, since it is so hotly arguable, I will leave it out of the toll.
  
: 'l'1 = "lover of anybody"
+
One more thing that we need to be duly wary about: There are many different conventions in the field as to the ordering of terms in their applications, and it happens that different conventions will be more convenient under different circumstances, so there does not appear to be much of a chance that any one of them can be canonized once and for all.
  
:: = (B:C +, C:B +, D:O +, E:I +, I:E +, O:D)(B +, C +, D +, E +, I +, J +, O)
+
In the current reading, we are applying relative terms from right to left, and so our conception of relative multiplication, or relational composition, will need to be adjusted accordingly.
  
:: = B +, C +, D +, E +, I +, O
+
===Commentary Note 8.4===
  
:: = "anybody except J"
+
To familiarize ourselves with the forms of calculation that are available in Peirce's notation, let us compute a few of the simplest products that we find at hand in the Othello case.
  
: 'l'b = "lover of a black"
+
Here are the absolute terms:
  
:: = (B:C +, C:B +, D:O +, E:I +, I:E +, O:D)O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{15}{c}}
 +
\mathbf{1}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{b}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{m}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{w}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
:: = D
+
Here are the 2-adic relative terms:
  
: 'l'm = "lover of a man"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{13}{c}}
 +
\mathit{l}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{B}:\mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{C}:\mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}:\mathrm{O}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}:\mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}:\mathrm{E}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}:\mathrm{D}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathit{s}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{C}:\mathrm{O}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}:\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}:\mathrm{O}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}:\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}:\mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
:: = (B:C +, C:B +, D:O +, E:I +, I:E +, O:D)(C +, I +, J +, O)
+
Here are a few of the simplest products among these terms:
  
:: = B +, D +, E
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathit{l}\mathbf{1}
 +
& = &
 +
\text{lover of anything}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{D})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
(\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\text{anything except}~\mathrm{J}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
: 'l'w = "lover of a woman"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathit{l}\mathrm{b}
 +
& = &
 +
\text{lover of a black}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{D})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{D}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
:: = (B:C +, C:B +, D:O +, E:I +, I:E +, O:D)(B +, D +, E)
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathit{l}\mathrm{m}
 +
& = &
 +
\text{lover of a man}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{D})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
(\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
:: = C +, I +, O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathit{l}\mathrm{w}
 +
& = &
 +
\text{lover of a woman}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{D})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
(\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
: 's'1 = "servant of anybody"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathit{s}\mathbf{1}
 +
& = &
 +
\text{servant of anything}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{O})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
(\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
:: = (C:O +, E:D +, I:O +, J:D +, J:O)(B +, C +, D +, E +, I +, J +, O)
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathit{s}\mathrm{b}
 +
& = &
 +
\text{servant of a black}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{O})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
:: = C +, E +, I +, J
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathit{s}\mathrm{m}
 +
& = &
 +
\text{servant of a man}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{O})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
(\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
: 's'b = "servant of a black"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathit{s}\mathrm{w}
 +
& = &
 +
\text{servant of a woman}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{O})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
(\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
:: = (C:O +, E:D +, I:O +, J:D +, J:O)O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathit{l}\mathit{s}
 +
& = &
 +
\text{lover of a servant of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{D})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{O})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{D}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
:: = C +, I +, J
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
+
|
: 's'm = "servant of a man"
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 
+
\mathit{s}\mathit{l}
:: = (C:O +, E:D +, I:O +, J:D +, J:O)(C +, I +, J +, O)
+
& = &
 
+
\text{servant of a lover of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
:: = C +, I +, J
+
\\[6pt]
 
+
& = &
: 's'w = "servant of a woman"
+
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{O})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
(\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{D})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
:: = (C:O +, E:D +, I:O +, J:D +, J:O)(B +, D +, E)
+
Among other things, one observes that the relative terms <math>\mathit{l}\!</math> and <math>\mathit{s}\!</math> do not commute, that is, <math>\mathit{l}\mathit{s}\!</math> is not equal to <math>\mathit{s}\mathit{l}.~\!</math>
 
 
:: = E +, J
 
 
 
: 'ls' = "lover of a servant of ---"
 
 
 
:: = (B:C +, C:B +, D:O +, E:I +, I:E +, O:D)(C:O +, E:D +, I:O +, J:D +, J:O)
 
 
 
:: = B:O +, E:O +, I:D
 
 
 
: 'sl' = "servant of a lover of ---"
 
 
 
:: = (C:O +, E:D +, I:O +, J:D +, J:O)(B:C +, C:B +, D:O +, E:I +, I:E +, O:D)
 
 
 
:: = C:D +, E:O +, I:D +, J:D +, J:O
 
 
 
Among other things, one observes that the relative terms 'l' and 's' do not commute, that is to say, 'ls' is not equal to 'sl'.
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 8.5===
 
===Commentary Note 8.5===
Line 664: Line 1,115:
 
Since multiplication by a 2-adic relative term is a logical analogue of matrix multiplication in linear algebra, all of the products that we computed above can be represented in terms of logical matrices and logical vectors.
 
Since multiplication by a 2-adic relative term is a logical analogue of matrix multiplication in linear algebra, all of the products that we computed above can be represented in terms of logical matrices and logical vectors.
  
Here are the absolute terms again, followed by their representation as "coefficient tuples", otherwise thought of as "coordinate vectors".
+
Here are the absolute terms again, followed by their representation as ''coefficient tuples'', otherwise thought of as ''coordinate vectors''.
  
: 1 = B +, C +, D +, E +, I +, J +, O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{ccrcccccccccccl}
 +
\mathbf{1}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[10pt]
 +
& = & (1 & , & 1 & , & 1 & , & 1 & , & 1 & , & 1 & , & 1)
 +
\\[20pt]
 +
\mathrm{b}
 +
& = &
 +
&  &
 +
&  &
 +
&  &
 +
&  &
 +
&  &
 +
&  &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[10pt]
 +
& = & (0 & , & 0 & , & 0 & , & 0 & , & 0 & , & 0 & , & 1)
 +
\\[20pt]
 +
\mathrm{m}
 +
& =      &
 +
&        & \mathrm{C}
 +
&        &
 +
&        &
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[10pt]
 +
& = & (0 & , & 1 & , & 0 & , & 0 & , & 1 & , & 1 & , & 1)
 +
\\[20pt]
 +
\mathrm{w}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{B}
 +
&        &
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
&        &
 +
&        &
 +
&        &
 +
\\[10pt]
 +
& = & (1 & , & 0 & , & 1 & , & 1 & , & 0 & , & 0 & , & 0)
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
:: = <1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1>
+
Since we are going to be regarding these tuples as ''column vectors'', it is convenient to arrange them into a table of the following form:
  
: b = O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
+
|
:: = <0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 1>
+
<math>\begin{array}{c|cccc}
 
+
\text{  } & \mathbf{1} & \mathrm{b} & \mathrm{m} & \mathrm{w}
: m = C +, I +, J +, O
+
\\
 
+
\text{---} & \text{---} & \text{---} & \text{---} & \text{---}
:: = <0, 1, 0, 0, 1, 1, 1>
+
\\
 
+
\mathrm{B} & 1 & 0 & 0 & 1
: w = B +, D +, E
+
\\
 
+
\mathrm{C} & 1 & 0 & 1 & 0
:: = <1, 0, 1, 1, 0, 0, 0>
+
\\
 
+
\mathrm{D} & 1 & 0 & 0 & 1
Since we are going to be regarding these tuples as "column vectors", it is convenient to arrange them into a table of the following form:
+
\\
 
+
\mathrm{E} & 1 & 0 & 0 & 1
<pre>
+
\\
  | 1 b m w
+
\mathrm{I} & 1 & 0 & 1 & 0
---o---------
+
\\
B | 1 0 0 1
+
\mathrm{J} & 1 & 0 & 1 & 0
C | 1 0 1 0
+
\\
D | 1 0 0 1
+
\mathrm{O} & 1 & 1 & 1 & 0
E | 1 0 0 1
+
\end{array}</math>
I | 1 0 1 0
+
|}
J | 1 0 1 0
 
O | 1 1 1 0
 
</pre>
 
  
 
Here are the 2-adic relative terms again, followed by their representation as coefficient matrices, in this case bordered by row and column labels to remind us what the coefficient values are meant to signify.
 
Here are the 2-adic relative terms again, followed by their representation as coefficient matrices, in this case bordered by row and column labels to remind us what the coefficient values are meant to signify.
  
: 'l' = B:C +, C:B +, D:O +, E:I +, I:E +, O:D =
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{13}{c}}
 +
\mathit{l}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{B}:\mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{C}:\mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}:\mathrm{O}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}:\mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}:\mathrm{E}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}:\mathrm{D}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
'l'| B C D E I J O
+
|
---o---------------
+
<math>\begin{array}{c|ccccccc}
B | 0 1 0 0 0 0 0
+
\mathit{l} &
C | 1 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
\mathrm{B} &
D | 0 0 0 0 0 0 1
+
\mathrm{C} &
E | 0 0 0 0 1 0 0
+
\mathrm{D} &
I | 0 0 0 1 0 0 0
+
\mathrm{E} &
J | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
\mathrm{I} &
O | 0 0 1 0 0 0 0
+
\mathrm{J} &
</pre>
+
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{B} & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{C} & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{D} & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{E} & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{I} & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{J} & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{O} & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
: 's' = C:O +, E:D +, I:O +, J:D +, J:O =
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{13}{c}}
 +
\mathit{s}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{C}:\mathrm{O}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}:\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}:\mathrm{O}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}:\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}:\mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
's'| B C D E I J O
+
|
---o---------------
+
<math>\begin{array}{c|ccccccc}
B | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
\mathit{s} &
C | 0 0 0 0 0 0 1
+
\mathrm{B} &
D | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
\mathrm{C} &
E | 0 0 1 0 0 0 0
+
\mathrm{D} &
I | 0 0 0 0 0 0 1
+
\mathrm{E} &
J | 0 0 1 0 0 0 1
+
\mathrm{I} &
O | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
\mathrm{J} &
</pre>
+
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---} &
 +
\text{---}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{B} & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{C} & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{D} & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{E} & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{I} & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{J} & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{O} & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
Here are the matrix representations of the products that we calculated before:
 
Here are the matrix representations of the products that we calculated before:
  
: 'l'1 = "lover of anybody" =
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathit{l}\mathbf{1} & = & \text{lover of anything} & =
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
| 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 1 |
+
|
| 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 1 |
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |  | 1 |
+
\mathit{l}\mathrm{b} & = & \text{lover of a black} & =
| 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 | | 1 | = | 1 |
+
\end{matrix}</math>
| 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 1 |
+
|-
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
|
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 1 |
+
<math>
</pre>
+
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
: 'l'b = "lover of a black" =
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathit{l}\mathrm{m} & = & \text{lover of a man} & =
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
1 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
| 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 0 |
+
|
| 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 0 |
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 0 |  | 1 |
+
\mathit{l}\mathrm{w} & = & \text{lover of a woman} & =
| 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 | | 0 | = | 0 |
+
\end{matrix}</math>
| 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 0 |
+
|-
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 0 |
+
|
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
<math>
</pre>
+
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
1 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}\!
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
: 'l'm = "lover of a man" =
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathit{s}\mathbf{1} & = & \text{servant of anything} & =
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
| 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 1 |
+
|
| 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 0 |  | 1 |
+
\mathit{s}\mathrm{b} & = & \text{servant of a black} & =
| 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 | | 0 | = | 1 |
+
\end{matrix}</math>
| 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
|-
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
|
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
<math>
</pre>
+
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
: 'l'w = "lover of a woman" =
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathit{s}\mathrm{m} & = & \text{servant of a man} & =
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
| 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
|
| 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 1 |
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
\mathit{s}\mathrm{w} & = & \text{servant of a woman} & =
| 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 | | 1 | = | 0 |
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
| 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 1 |
+
|-
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 0 |
+
|
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 1 |
+
<math>
</pre>
+
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
1 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
: 's'1 = "servant of anybody" =
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathit{l}\mathit{s} & = & \text{lover of a servant of ---} & =
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
|
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |  | 1 |
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
\mathit{s}\mathit{l} & = & \text{servant of a lover of ---} & =
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 1 | = | 1 |
+
\end{matrix}</math>
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |  | 1 |
+
|-
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |  | 1 |
+
|
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
<math>
</pre>
+
\begin{bmatrix}
 
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
: 's'b = "servant of a black" =
+
\\
 
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
<pre>
+
\\
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 0 |
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 0 |  | 1 |
+
\\
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 0 |
+
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 0 | = | 0 |
+
\\
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 0 |  | 1 |
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 | | 0 |  | 1 |
+
\\
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
</pre>
+
\\
 
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
: 's'm = "servant of a man" =
+
\end{bmatrix}
 
+
\begin{bmatrix}
<pre>
+
0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 0 |
+
\\
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |  | 1 |
+
1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 0 |
+
\\
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 0 | = | 0 |
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |  | 1 |
+
\\
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |  | 1 |
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
\\
</pre>
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0
 
+
\\
: 's'w = "servant of a woman" =
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 
+
\\
<pre>
+
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
\end{bmatrix}
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 0 |  | 0 |
+
=
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  | 0 |
+
\begin{bmatrix}
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 1 | = | 1 |
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 0 |  | 0 |
+
\\
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 | | 0 |  | 1 |
+
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  | 0 |
+
\\
</pre>
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 
+
\\
: 'ls' = "lover of a servant of ---" =
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 
+
\\
<pre>
+
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
| 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 |  | 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 |
+
\\
| 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 |  | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 |
+
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 |  | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 |
+
\\
| 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 | | 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | = | 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 |
+
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
| 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 | | 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 |  | 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 |
+
\end{bmatrix}
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 |  | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 |
+
</math>
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 |  | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 |
+
|}
</pre>
 
 
 
: 'sl' = "servant of a lover of ---" =
 
 
 
<pre>
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 |  | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 |  | 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 |  | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 |
 
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 | = | 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 |  | 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 |
 
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 | | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 |  | 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 |  | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 |
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 8.6===
 
===Commentary Note 8.6===
  
The foregoing has hopefully filled in enough background that we can begin to make sense of the more mysterious parts of CP 3.73.
+
The foregoing has hopefully filled in enough background that we can begin to make sense of the more mysterious parts of CP&nbsp;3.73.
  
<blockquote>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 +
|
 
<p>Thus far, we have considered the multiplication of relative terms only.  Since our conception of multiplication is the application of a relation, we can only multiply absolute terms by considering them as relatives.</p>
 
<p>Thus far, we have considered the multiplication of relative terms only.  Since our conception of multiplication is the application of a relation, we can only multiply absolute terms by considering them as relatives.</p>
  
<p>Now the absolute term "man" is really exactly equivalent to the relative term "man that is ---", and so with any other.  I shall write a comma after any absolute term to show that it is so regarded as a relative term.</p>
+
<p>Now the absolute term &ldquo;man&rdquo; is really exactly equivalent to the relative term &ldquo;man that is&nbsp;&mdash;&mdash;&rdquo;, and so with any other.  I shall write a comma after any absolute term to show that it is so regarded as a relative term.</p>
 
 
<p>Then:</p>
 
 
 
: <p>"man that is black"</p>
 
 
 
<p>will be written</p>
 
 
 
: <p>m,b.</p>
 
  
 +
<p>Then &ldquo;man that is black&rdquo; will be written:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{m},\!\mathrm{b}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.73).</p>
 
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.73).</p>
</blockquote>
+
|}
  
In any system where elements are organized according to types, there tend to be any number of ways in which elements of one type are naturally associated with elements of another type.  If the association is anything like a logical equivalence, but with the first type being "lower" and the second type being "higher" in some sense, then one frequently speaks of a "semantic ascent" from the lower to the higher type.
+
In any system where elements are organized according to types, there tend to be any number of ways in which elements of one type are naturally associated with elements of another type.  If the association is anything like a logical equivalence, but with the first type being lower and the second type being higher in some sense, then one may speak of a ''semantic ascent'' from the lower to the higher type.
  
For instance, it is very common in mathematics to associate an element ''m'' of a set ''M'' with the constant function ''f''<sub>''m''</sub>&nbsp;:&nbsp;''X''&nbsp;&rarr;&nbsp;''M'' such that ''f''<sub>''m''</sub>(''x'')&nbsp;=&nbsp;''m'' for all ''x'' in ''X'', where ''X'' is an arbitrary set.  Indeed, the correspondence is so close that one often uses the same name "''m''" for the element ''m'' in ''M'' and the function ''m'' = ''f''<sub>''m''</sub>&nbsp;:&nbsp;''X''&nbsp;&rarr;&nbsp;''M'', relying on the context or an explicit type indication to tell them apart.
+
For example, it is common in mathematics to associate an element <math>a\!</math> of a set <math>A\!</math> with the constant function <math>f_a : X \to A</math> that has <math>f_a (x) = a\!</math> for all <math>x\!</math> in <math>X,\!</math> where <math>X\!</math> is an arbitrary set.  Indeed, the correspondence is so close that one often uses the same name <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} a {}^{\prime\prime}</math> to denote both the element <math>a\!</math> in <math>A\!</math> and the function <math>a = f_a : X \to A,</math> relying on the context or an explicit type indication to tell them apart.
  
For another instance, we have the "tacit extension" of a ''k''-place relation ''L''&nbsp;&sube;&nbsp;''X''<sub>1</sub>&nbsp;&times;&nbsp;&hellip;&nbsp;&times;&nbsp;''X''<sub>''k''</sub> to a (''k''+1)-place relation ''L''&prime;&nbsp;&sube;&nbsp;''X''<sub>1</sub>&nbsp;&times;&nbsp;&hellip;&nbsp;&times;&nbsp;''X''<sub>''k''+1</sub> that
+
For another example, we have the ''tacit extension'' of a <math>k\!</math>-place relation <math>L \subseteq X_1 \times \ldots \times X_k\!</math> to a <math>(k+1)\!</math>-place relation <math>L^\prime \subseteq X_1 \times \ldots \times X_{k+1}\!</math> that we get by letting <math>L^\prime = L \times X_{k+1},</math> that is, by maintaining the constraints of <math>L\!</math> on the first <math>k\!</math> variables and letting the last variable wander freely.
we get by letting ''L''&prime; = ''L''&nbsp;&times;&nbsp;''X''<sub>''k''+1&nbsp;</sub>, that is, by maintaining the constraints
 
of ''L'' on the first ''k'' variables and letting the last variable wander freely.
 
  
What we have here, if I understand Peirce correctly, is another such type of natural extension, sometimes called the "diagonal extension".  This associates a ''k''-adic relative or a ''k''-adic relation, counting the absolute term and the set whose elements it denotes as the cases for ''k'' = 0, with a series of relatives and relations of higher adicities.
+
What we have here, if I understand Peirce correctly, is another such type of natural extension, sometimes called the ''diagonal extension''.  This extension associates a <math>k\!</math>-adic relative or a <math>k\!</math>-adic relation, counting the absolute term and the set whose elements it denotes as the cases for <math>k = 0,\!</math> with a series of relatives and relations of higher adicities.
  
 
A few examples will suffice to anchor these ideas.
 
A few examples will suffice to anchor these ideas.
Line 882: Line 1,703:
 
Absolute terms:
 
Absolute terms:
  
: m = "man" = C +, I +, J +, O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
+
|
: n = "noble" = C +, D +, O
+
<math>\begin{array}{*{11}{c}}
 
+
\mathrm{m}
: w = "woman" = B +, D +, E
+
& =     & \text{man}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{n}
 +
& =     & \text{noble}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{w}
 +
& =     & \text{woman}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
Diagonal extensions:
 
Diagonal extensions:
  
: m, = "man that is ---"    = C:C +, I:I +, J:J +, O:O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
+
|
: n, = "noble that is ---"  = C:C +, D:D +, O:O
+
<math>\begin{array}{*{11}{c}}
 
+
\mathrm{m,}
: w, = "woman that is ---"  = B:B +, D:D +, E:E
+
& =     & \text{man that is}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{C}:\mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}:\mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}:\mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}:\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{n,}
 +
& =     & \text{noble that is}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{C}:\mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}:\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}:\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{w,}
 +
& =     & \text{woman that is}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{B}:\mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}:\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}:\mathrm{E}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
Sample products:
 
Sample products:
  
: m,n = "man that is noble
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathrm{m},\!\mathrm{n}
 +
& = &
 +
\text{man that is noble}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
(\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
:: = (C:C +, I:I +, J:J +, O:O)(C +, D +, O)
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathrm{n},\!\mathrm{m}
 +
& = &
 +
\text{noble that is a man}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
(\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
:: = C +, O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathrm{w},\!\mathrm{n}
 +
& = &
 +
\text{woman that is noble}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{E})
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
& &
 +
(\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{D}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
: n,m = "noble that is man"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
+
|
:: = (C:C +, D:D +, O:O)(C +, I +, J +, O)
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 
+
\mathrm{n},\!\mathrm{w}
:: = C +, O
+
& = &
 
+
\text{noble that is a woman}
: n,w = "noble that is woman"
+
\\[6pt]
 
+
& = &
:: = (C:C +, D:D +, O:O)(B +, D +, E)
+
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O})
 
+
\\
:: = D
+
& &
 
+
\times
: w,n = "woman that is noble"
+
\\
 
+
& &
:: = (B:B +, D:D +, E:E)(C +, D +, O)
+
(\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E})
 
+
\\[6pt]
:: = D
+
& = &
 +
\mathrm{D}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
==Selection 9==
 
==Selection 9==
  
<blockquote>
+
===The Signs for Multiplication (cont.)===
<p>'''The Signs for Multiplication''' (cont.)</p>
 
  
<p>It is obvious that multiplication into a multiplicand indicated by a comma is commutative¹, that is,</p>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 
+
|
: <p>'s','l= 'l','s'.</p>
+
<p>It is obvious that multiplication into a multiplicand indicated by a comma is commutative<sup>1</sup>, that is,</p>
 
+
|-
<p>This multiplication is effectively the same as that of Boole in his logical calculus.  Boole's unity is my 1, that is, it denotes whatever is.</p>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{s},\!\mathit{l} ~=~ \mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>This multiplication is effectively the same as that of Boole in his logical calculus.  Boole's unity is my <math>\mathbf{1},</math> that is, it denotes whatever is.</p>
  
# <p>It will often be convenient to speak of the whole operation of affixing a comma and then multiplying as a commutative multiplication, the sign for which is the comma.  But though this is allowable, we shall fall into confusion at once if we ever forget that in point of fact it is not a different multiplication, only it is multiplication by a relative whose meaning or rather whose syntax has been slightly altered;  and that the comma is really the sign of this modification of the foregoing term.</p>
+
#<p>It will often be convenient to speak of the whole operation of affixing a comma and then multiplying as a commutative multiplication, the sign for which is the comma.  But though this is allowable, we shall fall into confusion at once if we ever forget that in point of fact it is not a different multiplication, only it is multiplication by a relative whose meaning &mdash; or rather whose syntax &mdash; has been slightly altered;  and that the comma is really the sign of this modification of the foregoing term.</p>
  
 
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.74).</p>
 
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.74).</p>
</blockquote>
+
|}
  
 
===Commentary Note 9.1===
 
===Commentary Note 9.1===
  
Let us backtrack a few years, and consider how Boole explained his twin conceptions of "selective operations" and "selective symbols".
+
Let us backtrack a few years, and consider how George Boole explained his twin conceptions of ''selective operations'' and ''selective symbols''.
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 +
|
 +
<p>Let us then suppose that the universe of our discourse is the actual universe, so that words are to be used in the full extent of their meaning, and let us consider the two mental operations implied by the words &ldquo;white&rdquo; and &ldquo;men&rdquo;.  The word &ldquo;men&rdquo; implies the operation of selecting in thought from its subject, the universe, all men;  and the resulting conception, ''men'', becomes the subject of the next operation.  The operation implied by the word &ldquo;white&rdquo; is that of selecting from its subject, &ldquo;men&rdquo;, all of that class which are white.  The final resulting conception is that of &ldquo;white men&rdquo;.</p>
  
<blockquote>
+
<p>Now it is perfectly apparent that if the operations above described had been performed in a converse order, the result would have been the same.  Whether we begin by forming the conception of &ldquo;''men''&rdquo;, and then by a second intellectual act limit that conception to &ldquo;white men&rdquo;, or whether we begin by forming the conception of &ldquo;white objects&rdquo;, and then limit it to such of that class as are &ldquo;men&rdquo;, is perfectly indifferent so far as the result is concerned.  It is obvious that the order of the mental processes would be equally indifferent if for the words &ldquo;white&rdquo; and &ldquo;men&rdquo; we substituted any other descriptive or appellative terms whatever, provided only that their meaning was fixed and absoluteAnd thus the indifference of the order of two successive acts of the faculty of Conception, the one of which furnishes the subject upon which the other is supposed to operate, is a general condition of the exercise of that facultyIt is a law of the mind, and it is the real origin of that law of the literal symbols of Logic which constitutes its formal expression (1) Chap. II, [&nbsp;namely, <math>xy = yx~\!</math>&nbsp;].</p>
<p>Let us then suppose that the universe of our discourse is the actual universe, so that words are to be used in the full extent of their meaning, and let us consider the two mental operations implied by the words "white" and "men"The word "men" implies the operation of selecting in thought from its subject, the universe, all men;  and the resulting conception, ''men'', becomes the subject of the next operationThe operation implied by the word "white" is that of selecting from its subject, "men", all of that class which are white.  The final resulting conception is that of "white men".</p>
 
  
<p>Now it is perfectly apparent that if the operations above described had been performed in a converse order, the result would have been the sameWhether we begin by forming the conception of "''men''", and then by a second intellectual act limit that conception to "white men", or whether we begin by forming the conception of "white objects", and then limit it to such of that class as are "men", is perfectly indifferent so far as the result is concernedIt is obvious that the order of the mental processes would be equally indifferent if for the words "white" and "men" we substituted any other descriptive or appellative terms whatever, provided only that their meaning was fixed and absolute.  And thus the indifference of the order of two successive acts of the faculty of Conception, the one of which furnishes the subject upon which the other is supposed to operate, is a general condition of the exercise of that facultyIt is a law of the mind, and it is the real origin of that law of the literal symbols of Logic which constitutes its formal expression (1) Chap. II, [namely, ''xy'' = ''yx''].</p>
+
<p>It is equally clear that the mental operation above described is of such a nature that its effect is not altered by repetitionSuppose that by a definite act of conception the attention has been fixed upon men, and that by another exercise of the same faculty we limit it to those of the race who are whiteThen any further repetition of the latter mental act, by which the attention is limited to white objects, does not in any way modify the conception arrived at, viz., that of white menThis is also an example of a general law of the mind, and it has its formal expression in the law ((2) Chap. II) of the literal symbols [&nbsp;namely, <math>x^2 = x\!</math>&nbsp;].</p>
  
<p>It is equally clear that the mental operation above described is of such a nature that its effect is not altered by repetition.  Suppose that by a definite act of conception the attention has been fixed upon men, and that by another exercise of the same faculty we limit it to those of the race who are white.  Then any further repetition of the latter mental act, by which the attention is limited to white objects, does not in any way modify the conception arrived at, viz., that of white men.  This is also an example of a general law of the mind, and it has its formal expression in the law ((2) Chap. II) of the literal symbols [namely, ''x''<sup>2</sup> = ''x''].  (Boole, ''Laws of Thought'', 44–45).</p>
+
<p>(Boole, ''Laws of Thought'', 44&ndash;45).</p>
</blockquote>
+
|}
  
 
===Commentary Note 9.2===
 
===Commentary Note 9.2===
Line 954: Line 1,876:
 
In setting up his discussion of selective operations and their corresponding selective symbols, Boole writes this:
 
In setting up his discussion of selective operations and their corresponding selective symbols, Boole writes this:
  
<blockquote>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
The operation which we really perform is one of ''selection according to a prescribed principle or idea''.  To what faculties of the mind such an operation would be referred, according to the received classification of its powers, it is not important to inquire, but I suppose that it would be considered as dependent upon the two faculties of Conception or Imagination, and Attention.  To the one of these faculties might be referred the formation of the general conception;  to the other the fixing of the mental regard upon those individuals within the prescribed universe of discourse which answer to the conception.  If, however, as seems not improbable, the power of Attention is nothing more than the power of continuing the exercise of any other faculty of the mind, we might properly regard the whole of the mental process above described as referrible to the mental faculty of Imagination or Conception, the first step of the process being the conception of the Universe itself, and each succeeding step limiting in a definite manner the conception thus formed.  Adopting this view, I shall describe each such step, or any definite combination of such steps, as a ''definite act of conception''. (Boole, ''Laws of Thought'', 43).
+
|
</blockquote>
+
<p>The operation which we really perform is one of ''selection according to a prescribed principle or idea''.  To what faculties of the mind such an operation would be referred, according to the received classification of its powers, it is not important to inquire, but I suppose that it would be considered as dependent upon the two faculties of Conception or Imagination, and Attention.  To the one of these faculties might be referred the formation of the general conception;  to the other the fixing of the mental regard upon those individuals within the prescribed universe of discourse which answer to the conception.  If, however, as seems not improbable, the power of Attention is nothing more than the power of continuing the exercise of any other faculty of the mind, we might properly regard the whole of the mental process above described as referrible to the mental faculty of Imagination or Conception, the first step of the process being the conception of the Universe itself, and each succeeding step limiting in a definite manner the conception thus formed.  Adopting this view, I shall describe each such step, or any definite combination of such steps, as a ''definite act of conception''.</p>
 +
 
 +
<p>(Boole, ''Laws of Thought'', 43).</p>
 +
|}
  
 
===Commentary Note 9.3===
 
===Commentary Note 9.3===
  
<pre>
+
In algebra, an ''idempotent element'' <math>x\!</math> is one that obeys the ''idempotent law'', that is, it satisfies the equation <math>xx = x.\!</math>  Under most circumstances, it is usual to write this as <math>x^2 = x.\!</math>
In algebra, an "idempotent element" x is one that obeys the
 
"idempotent law", that is, it satisfies the equation xx = x.
 
Under most circumstances, it is usual to write this x^2 = x.
 
  
If the algebraic system in question falls under the additional laws
+
If the algebraic system in question falls under the additional laws that are necessary to carry out the requisite transformations, then <math>x^2 = x\!</math> is convertible into <math>x - x^2 = 0,\!</math> and this into <math>x(1 - x) = 0.\!</math>
that are necessary to carry out the requisite transformations, then
 
x^2 = x is convertible into x - x^2 = 0, and this into x(1 - x) = 0.
 
  
If the algebraic system in question happens to be a boolean algebra,
+
If the algebraic system in question happens to be a boolean algebra, then the equation <math>x(1 - x) = 0\!</math> says that <math>x \land \lnot x</math> is identically false, in effect, a statement of the classical principle of non-contradiction.
then the equation x(1 - x) = 0 says that x & ~x is identically false,
 
in effect, a statement of the classical principle of non-contradiction.
 
  
We have already seen how Boole found rationales for the commutative law and
+
We have already seen how Boole found rationales for the commutative law and the idempotent law by contemplating the properties of ''selective operations''.
the idempotent law by contemplating the properties of "selective operations".
 
  
It is time to bring these threads together, which we can do by considering the
+
It is time to bring these threads together, which we can do by considering the so-called ''idempotent representation'' of sets.  This will give us one of the best ways to understand the significance that Boole attached to selective operations.  It will also link up with the statements that Peirce makes about his adicity-augmenting comma operation.
so-called "idempotent representation" of sets.  This will give us one of the
 
best ways to understand the significance that Boole attached to selective
 
operations.  It will also link up with the statements that Peirce makes
 
about his adicity-augmenting comma operation.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 9.4===
 
===Commentary Note 9.4===
  
<pre>
+
Boole rationalized the properties of what we now call ''boolean multiplication'', roughly equivalent to logical conjunction, in terms of the laws that apply to selective operations.  Peirce, in his turn, taking a very significant step of analysis that has seldom been recognized for what it would lead to, does not consider this multiplication to be a fundamental operation, but derives it as a by-product of relative multiplication by a comma relative. Thus, Peirce makes logical conjunction a special case of relative composition.
Boole rationalized the properties of what we now dub "boolean multiplication",
 
roughly equivalent to logical conjunction, in terms of the laws that apply to
 
selective operations.  Peirce, in his turn, taking a very significant step of
 
analysis that has seldom been recognized for what it would lead to, much less
 
followed, does not consider this multiplication to be a fundamental operation,
 
but derives it as a by-product of relative multiplication by a comma relative.
 
Thus, Peirce makes logical conjunction a special case of relative composition.
 
  
This opens up a very wide field of investigation,
+
This opens up a very wide field of investigation, ''the operational significance of logical terms'', one might say, but it will be best to advance bit by bit, and to lean on simple examples.
"the operational significance of logical terms",
 
one might say, but it will be best to advance
 
bit by bit, and to lean on simple examples.
 
  
Back to Venice, and the close-knit party
+
Back to Venice, and the close-knit party of absolutes and relatives that we were entertaining when last we were there.
of absolutes and relatives that we were
 
entertaining when last we were there.
 
  
Here is the list of absolute terms that we were considering before,
+
Here is the list of absolute terms that we were considering before, to which I have thrown in <math>\mathbf{1},</math> the universe of ''anything'', just for good measure:
to which I have thrown in 1, the universe of "anybody or anything",
 
just for good measure:
 
  
= "anybody"             = B +, C +, D +, E +, I +, J +, O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{17}{l}}
 +
\mathbf{1}
 +
& =     & \text{anything}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{m}
 +
& =      & \text{man}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{n}
 +
& =      & \text{noble}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{w}
 +
& =      & \text{woman}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
m  =  "man"                  =  C +, I +, J +, O
+
Here is the list of ''comma inflexions'' or ''diagonal extensions'' of these terms:
  
n   = "noble"                = C +, D +, O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathbf{1,}
 +
& = & \text{anything that is}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[9pt]
 +
\mathrm{m,}
 +
& = & \text{man that is}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[9pt]
 +
\mathrm{n,}
 +
& = & \text{noble that is}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[9pt]
 +
\mathrm{w,}
 +
& = & \text{woman that is}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{E}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
w  =  "woman"                =  B +, D +, E
+
One observes that the diagonal extension of <math>\mathbf{1}</math> is the same thing as the identity relation <math>\mathit{1}.\!</math>
  
Here is the list of "comma inflexions" or "diagonal extensions" of these terms:
+
Working within our smaller sample of absolute terms, we have already computed the sorts of products that apply the diagonal extension of an absolute term to another absolute term, for instance, these products:
  
1, = "anybody that is ---"  = B:B +, C:C +, D:D +, E:E +, I:I +, J:J +, O:O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lllll}
 +
\mathrm{m},\!\mathrm{n}
 +
& = & \text{man that is noble}
 +
& = & \mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{n},\!\mathrm{m}
 +
& = & \text{noble that is a man}
 +
& = & \mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{w},\!\mathrm{n}
 +
& = & \text{woman that is noble}
 +
& = & \mathrm{D}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{n},\!\mathrm{w}
 +
& = & \text{noble that is a woman}
 +
& = & \mathrm{D}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
m,  =  "man that is ---"      =  C:C +, I:I +, J:J +, O:O
+
This exercise gave us a bit of practical insight into why the commutative law holds for logical conjunction.
  
n, =  "noble that is ---"    =  C:C +, D:D +, O:O
+
Further insight into the laws that govern this realm of logic, and the underlying reasons why they apply, might be gained by systematically working through the whole variety of different products that are generated by the operational means in sight, namely, the products indicated by <math>\{\mathbf{1}, \mathrm{m}, \mathrm{n}, \mathrm{w} \} , \{\mathbf{1}, \mathrm{m}, \mathrm{n}, \mathrm{w} \}.</math>
  
w,  =  "woman that is ---"    =  B:B +, D:D +, E:E
+
But before we try to explore this territory more systematically, let us equip our intuitions with the forms of graphical and matrical representation that served us so well in our previous adventures.
 
 
One observes that the diagonal extension of 1
 
is the same thing as the identity relation !1!.
 
 
 
Inspired by this identification of "1," with "!1!", and because
 
the affixed commas of the diagonal extensions tend to get lost
 
in the ordinary commas of punctuation, I will experiment with
 
using the alternative notations:
 
 
 
m,  =  !m!
 
n,  =  !n!
 
w,  =  !w!
 
 
 
Working within our smaller sample of absolute terms,
 
we have already computed the sorts of products that
 
apply the diagonal extension of an absolute term to
 
another absolute term, for instance, these products:
 
 
 
m,n  =  !m!n  =  "man that is noble"    =  C +, O
 
n,m  =  !n!m  =  "noble that is man"    =  C +, O
 
n,w  =  !n!w  =  "noble that is woman"  =  D
 
w,n  =  !w!n  =  "woman that is noble"  =  D
 
 
 
This exercise gave us a bit of practical insight into
 
why the commutative law holds for logical conjunction.
 
 
 
Further insight into the laws that govern this realm of logic,
 
and the underlying reasons why they apply, might be gained by
 
systematically working through the whole variety of different
 
products that are generated by the operational means in sight,
 
namely, the products indicated by {1, m, n, w}<,>{1, m, n, w}.
 
 
 
But before we try to explore this territory more systematically,
 
let us equip ourselves with the sorts of graphical and matrical
 
representations that we discovered to provide us with such able
 
assists to the intuition in so many of our previous adventures.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 9.5===
 
===Commentary Note 9.5===
  
<pre>
+
Peirce's comma operation, in its application to an absolute term, is tantamount to the representation of that term's denotation as an idempotent transformation, which is commonly represented as a diagonal matrix.  Hence the alternate name, ''diagonal extension''.
Peirce's comma operation, in its application to an absolute term,
 
is tantamount to the representation of that term's denotation as
 
an idempotent transformation, which is commonly represented as a
 
diagonal matrix.  This is why I call it the "diagonal extension".
 
  
An idempotent element x is given by the abstract condition that xx = x,
+
An idempotent element <math>x\!</math> is given by the abstract condition that <math>xx = x,\!</math> but elements like these are commonly encountered in more concrete circumstances, acting as operators or transformations on other sets or spaces, and in that action they will often be represented as matrices of coefficients.
but we commonly encounter such elements in more concrete circumstances,
 
acting as operators or transformations on other sets or spaces, and in
 
that action they will often be represented as matrices of coefficients.
 
  
Let's see how all of this looks from the graphical and matrical perspectives.
+
Let's see how this looks in the matrix and graph pictures of absolute and relative terms:
  
Absolute terms:
+
====Absolute Terms====
  
= "anybody" = B +, C +, D +, E +, I +, J +, O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{17}{l}}
 +
\mathbf{1} & = & \text{anything} & = &
 +
\mathrm{B} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{C} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{D} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{E} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{I} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{J} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{m} & = & \text{man} & = &
 +
\mathrm{C} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{I} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{J} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{n} & = & \text{noble} & = &
 +
\mathrm{C} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{D} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{w} & = & \text{woman} & = &
 +
\mathrm{B} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{D} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{E}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
m  =  "man"      = C +, I +, J +, O
+
Previously, we represented absolute terms as column arrays. The above four terms are given by the columns of the following table:
  
= "noble"   = C +, D +, O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{c|cccc}
 +
\text{  } & \mathbf{1} & \mathrm{m} & \mathrm{n} & \mathrm{w} \\
 +
\text{---} & \text{---} & \text{---} & \text{---} & \text{---} \\
 +
\mathrm{B} & 1 & 0 & 0 & 1 \\
 +
\mathrm{C} & 1 & 1 & 1 & 0 \\
 +
\mathrm{D} & 1 & 0 & 1 & 1 \\
 +
\mathrm{E} & 1 & 0 & 0 & 1 \\
 +
\mathrm{I} & 1 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\
 +
\mathrm{J} & 1 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\
 +
\mathrm{O} & 1 & 1 & 1 & 0
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
w =  "woman"    =  B +, D +, E
+
The types of graphs known as ''bigraphs'' or ''bipartite graphs'' can be used to picture simple relative terms, dyadic relations, and their corresponding logical matrices. One way to bring absolute terms and their corresponding sets of individuals into the bigraph picture is to mark the nodes in some way, for example, hollow nodes for non-members and filled nodes for members of the indicated set, as shown below:
  
Previously, we represented absolute terms as column vectors.
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" width="90%"
The above four terms are given by the columns of this table:
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 4.1.jpg]] || (4.1)
 +
|-
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 4.2.jpg]] || (4.2)
 +
|-
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 4.3.jpg]] || (4.3)
 +
|-
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 4.4.jpg]] || (4.4)
 +
|}
  
  | 1 m n w
+
====Diagonal Extensions====
---o---------
 
B | 1 0 0 1
 
C | 1 1 1 0
 
D | 1 0 1 1
 
E | 1 0 0 1
 
I | 1 1 0 0
 
J | 1 1 0 0
 
O | 1 1 1 0
 
  
One way to represent sets in the bigraph picture
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
is simply to mark the nodes in some way, like so:
+
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathbf{1,}
 +
& = & \text{anything that is}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[9pt]
 +
\mathrm{m,}
 +
& = & \text{man that is}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[9pt]
 +
\mathrm{n,}
 +
& = & \text{noble that is}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[9pt]
 +
\mathrm{w,}
 +
& = & \text{woman that is}\, \underline{~~ ~~}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{E}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
    B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
Naturally enough, the diagonal extensions are represented by diagonal matrices:
1  +  +  +  +  +  +  +
 
  
    B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
m   o   +   o   o   +   +  +
+
|
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{c|ccccccc}
 +
\mathbf{1,} &
 +
\mathrm{B}  &
 +
\mathrm{C}  &
 +
\mathrm{D}  &
 +
\mathrm{E}  &
 +
\mathrm{I}  &
 +
\mathrm{J}  &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{B} & 1 &  &  &  &  &   &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{C} &   & 1 &  &  &  &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{D} &  &  & 1 &  &   &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{E} &   &  &  & 1 &  &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{I} &   &  &  &  & 1 &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{J} &  &   &  &  &  & 1 &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{O} &   &   &   &   &   &   & 1
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
    B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
n   o   +   +   o   o   o  +
+
|
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{c|ccccccc}
 +
\mathrm{m,} &
 +
\mathrm{B}  &
 +
\mathrm{C}  &
 +
\mathrm{D}  &
 +
\mathrm{E}  &
 +
\mathrm{I}  &
 +
\mathrm{J}  &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{B} & 0 &  &  &  &  &   &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{C} &   & 1 &  &  &  &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{D} &  &  & 0 &  &   &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{E} &   &  &  & 0 &  &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{I} &   &  &  &  & 1 &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{J} &  &   &  &  &  & 1 &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{O} &   &   &   &   &   &   & 1
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
    B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
w   +   o   +   +   o   o  o
+
|
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{c|ccccccc}
 +
\mathrm{n,} &
 +
\mathrm{B}  &
 +
\mathrm{C}  &
 +
\mathrm{D}  &
 +
\mathrm{E}  &
 +
\mathrm{I}  &
 +
\mathrm{J}  &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{B} & 0 &  &  &  &  &   &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{C} &   & 1 &  &  &  &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{D} &  &  & 1 &  &   &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{E} &   &  &  & 0 &  &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{I} &   &  &  &  & 0 &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{J} &  &   &  &  &  & 0 &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{O} &   &   &   &   &   &   & 1
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
Diagonal extensions of the absolute terms:
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{c|ccccccc}
 +
\mathrm{w,} &
 +
\mathrm{B}  &
 +
\mathrm{C}  &
 +
\mathrm{D}  &
 +
\mathrm{E}  &
 +
\mathrm{I}  &
 +
\mathrm{J}  &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}  &
 +
\text{---}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{B} & 1 &  &  &  &  &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{C} &  & 0 &  &  &  &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{D} &  &  & 1 &  &  &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{E} &  &  &  & 1 &  &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{I} &  &  &  &  & 0 &  &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{J} &  &  &  &  &  & 0 &
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{O} &  &  &  &  &  &  & 0
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
1, =  "anybody that is ---"  =  B:B +, C:C +, D:D +, E:E +, I:I +, J:J +, O:O
+
Cast into the bigraph picture of dyadic relations, the diagonal extension of an absolute term takes on a very distinctive sort of &ldquo;straight-laced&rdquo; character:
  
m,  = "man that is ---"     = C:C +, I:I +, J:J +, O:O
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" width="90%"
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 5.1.jpg]] || (5.1)
 +
|-
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 5.2.jpg]] || (5.2)
 +
|-
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 5.3.jpg]] || (5.3)
 +
|-
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 5.4.jpg]] || (5.4)
 +
|}
  
n,  = "noble that is ---"    = C:C +, D:D +, O:O
+
===Commentary Note 9.6===
  
w, =  "woman that is ---"    =  B:B +, D:D +, E:E
+
Just to be doggedly persistent about it, here is what ought to be a sufficient sample of products involving the multiplication of a comma relative onto an absolute term, presented in both matrix and bigraph pictures.
  
Naturally enough, the diagonal extensions are represented by diagonal matrices:
+
====Example 1====
  
!1!| B C D E I J O
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
---o---------------
+
| <math>\mathbf{1,}\mathbf{1} ~=~ \mathbf{1}\!</math>
B | 1 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
|-
C | 0 1 0 0 0 0 0
+
| <math>\text{anything that is anything} ~=~ \text{anything}</math>
D | 0 0 1 0 0 0 0
+
|-
E | 0 0 0 1 0 0 0
+
|
I | 0 0 0 0 1 0 0
+
<math>
J | 0 0 0 0 0 1 0
+
\begin{bmatrix}
O | 0 0 0 0 0 0 1
+
1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
!m!| B C D E I J O
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" width="100%"
---o---------------
+
| width="2%" | &nbsp;
B | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
| width="48%" | [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 6.1.jpg]]
C | 0 1 0 0 0 0 0
+
| width="50%" | (6.1)
  D | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
|}
E | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
 
I | 0 0 0 0 1 0 0
 
J | 0 0 0 0 0 1 0
 
O | 0 0 0 0 0 0 1
 
  
!n!| B C D E I J O
+
====Example 2====
---o---------------
 
B | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
 
C | 0 1 0 0 0 0 0
 
D | 0 0 1 0 0 0 0
 
E | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
 
I | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
 
J | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
 
O | 0 0 0 0 0 0 1
 
  
!w!| B C D E I J O
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
---o---------------
+
| <math>\mathbf{1,}\mathrm{m} ~=~ \mathrm{m}</math>
B | 1 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
|-
C | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
| <math>\text{anything that is a man} ~=~ \text{man}</math>
D | 0 0 1 0 0 0 0
+
|-
E | 0 0 0 1 0 0 0
+
|
I | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
<math>
J | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
\begin{bmatrix}
O | 0 0 0 0 0 0 0
+
1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
Cast into the bigraph picture of 2-adic relations,
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" width="100%"
the diagonal extension of an absolute term takes on
+
| width="2%"  | &nbsp;
a very distinctive sort of "straight-laced" character:
+
| width="48%" | [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 6.2.jpg]]
 +
| width="50%" | (6.2)
 +
|}
  
    B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
====Example 3====
u  o  o  o  o  o  o  o
 
    |  |  |  |  |  |  |
 
1,  |  |  |  |  |  |  |
 
    |  |  |  |  |  |  |
 
u  o  o  o  o  o  o  o
 
    B  C  D  E  I  J  O
 
  
    B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
u  o  o  o  o  o  o  o
+
| <math>\mathrm{m,}\mathbf{1} ~=~ \mathrm{m}</math>
        |          |  |  |
+
|-
m,     |           |   |   |
+
| <math>\text{man that is anything} ~=~ \text{man}</math>
        |          |  |  |
+
|-
u  o  o  o  o  o  o  o
+
|
    B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
<math>
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
    B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" width="100%"
u  o  o  o  o  o  o  o
+
| width="2%"  | &nbsp;
        |  |               |
+
| width="48%" | [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 6.3.jpg]]
n,      |   |              |
+
| width="50%" | (6.3)
        |   |               |
+
|}
u  o  o  o  o  o  o  o
 
    B  C  D  E  I  J  O
 
  
    B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
====Example 4====
u  o  o  o  o  o  o  o
 
    |      |  |
 
w,  |      |  |
 
    |      |  |
 
u  o  o  o  o  o  o  o
 
    B  C  D  E  I  J  O
 
</pre>
 
  
===Commentary Note 9.6===
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{n} ~=~ \text{man that is noble}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" width="100%"
Just to be doggedly persistent about it all, here is what
+
| width="2%"  | &nbsp;
ought to be a sufficient sample of products involving the
+
| width="48%" | [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 6.4.jpg]]
multiplication of a comma relative onto an absolute term,
+
| width="50%" | (6.4)
presented in both graphical and matrical representations.
+
|}
  
Example 1.  Anything That Is Anything
+
====Example 5====
  
1,1 = 1
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>\mathrm{n,}\mathrm{m} ~=~ \text{noble that is a man}</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1 \\ 1 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
=
 +
\begin{bmatrix}
 +
0 \\ 1 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 0 \\ 1
 +
\end{bmatrix}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
"anything that is anything"  = "anything"
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" width="100%"
 +
| width="2%| &nbsp;
 +
| width="48%" | [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 6.5.jpg]]
 +
| width="50%" | (6.5)
 +
|}
  
B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
===Commentary Note 9.7===
+  +  +  +  +  +  +  1
 
|  |  |  |  |  |  |
 
|  |  |  |  |  |  |  1,
 
|  |  |  |  |  |  |
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  =
 
  
+  +  +  +  +  +  + 1
+
From this point forward we may think of idempotents, selectives, and zero-one diagonal matrices as being roughly equivalent notions. The only reason that I say ''roughly'' is that we are comparing ideas at different levels of abstraction in proposing these connections.
B  C  D  E  I   J  O
 
  
| 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |    | 1 |
+
We have covered the way that Peirce uses his invention of the comma modifier to assimilate boolean multiplication, logical conjunction, and what we may think of as ''serial selection'' under his more general account of relative multiplication.
| 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
| 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 | | 1 |  =  | 1 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
  
Example 2Anything That Is Man
+
But the comma functor has its application to relative terms of any arity, not just the zeroth arity of absolute terms, and so there will be a lot more to explore on this pointBut now I must return to the anchorage of Peirce's text and hopefully get a chance to revisit this topic later.
  
1,m  = m
+
==Selection 10==
  
"anything that is man"  = "man"
+
===The Signs for Multiplication (cont.)===
  
B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
o  +  o  o  +  +  +  m
+
|
|  |  |  |  |  |  |
+
<p>The sum <math>x + x\!</math> generally denotes no logical term. But <math>{x,}_\infty + \, {x,}_\infty</math> may be considered as denoting some two <math>x\!</math>'s.</p>
|  |  |  |  |  |  | 1,
 
|  |  |  |  |  |  |
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  =
 
  
o  +  o  o  +  +  +  m
+
<p>It is natural to write:</p>
B  C  D  E  I  J  O
 
  
| 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |     | 0 |
+
{| align="center" width="100%"
| 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |     | 1 |
+
| width="20%" | &nbsp;
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |    | 0 |
+
| width="25%" align="right" | <math>x ~+~ x</math>
| 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 | | 0 |  =  | 0 |
+
| width="10%" align="center"| <math>=\!</math>
| 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 | | 1 |    | 1 |
+
| width="25%" align="left"  | <math>\mathit{2}.x\!</math>
| 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 | | 1 |    | 1 |
+
| width="20%" | &nbsp;
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |    | 1 |
+
|-
 +
|
 +
|-
 +
| and
 +
| align="right" | <math>{x,}_\infty + \, {x,}_\infty</math>
 +
| align="center" | <math>=\!</math>
 +
| align="left"  | <math>\mathit{2}.{x,}_\infty</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|}
  
Example 3. Man That Is Anything
+
<p>where the dot shows that this multiplication is invertible.</p>
  
m,1  =  m
+
<p>We may also use the antique figures so that:</p>
  
"man that is anything"  =  "man"
+
{| align="center" width="100%"
 +
| width="20%" | &nbsp;
 +
| width="25%" align="right" | <math>\mathit{2}.{x,}_\infty</math>
 +
| width="10%" align="center"| <math>=\!</math>
 +
| width="25%" align="left| <math>\mathfrak{2}x</math>
 +
| width="20%" | &nbsp;
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
|-
 +
| just as
 +
| align="right" | <math>\mathit{1}_\infty</math>
 +
| align="center" | <math>=\!</math>
 +
| align="left"   | <math>\mathfrak{1}</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|}
  
B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
<p>Then <math>\mathfrak{2}</math> alone will denote some two things.</p>
+  +  +  +  +  +  +  1
 
    |          |  |  |
 
    |          |  |  |  m,
 
    |          |  |  |
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  =
 
  
o  +  o  o  +  +  +  m
+
<p>But this multiplication is not in general commutative, and only becomes so when it affects a relative which imparts a relation such that a thing only bears it to ''one'' thing, and one thing ''alone'' bears it to a thing.</p>
B  C  D  E  I  J  O
 
  
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |    | 0 |
+
<p>For instance, the lovers of two women are not the same as two lovers of women, that is:</p>
| 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |    | 0 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |  =  | 0 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
  
Example 4Man That Is Noble
+
{| align="center" width="100%"
 +
| width="20%" | &nbsp;
 +
| width="25%" align="right" | <math>\mathit{l}\mathfrak{2}.\mathrm{w}</math>
 +
| width="10%" align="center"| and
 +
| width="25%" align="left" | <math>\mathfrak{2}.\mathit{l}\mathrm{w}</math>
 +
| width="20%" | &nbsp;
 +
|}
  
m,n  =  "man that is noble"
+
<p>are unequal;  but the husbands of two women are the same as two husbands of women, that is:</p>
  
B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
{| align="center" width="100%"
o  +  +  o  o  o  + n
+
| width="20%" | &nbsp;
    |           |   |   |
+
| width="25%" align="right" | <math>\mathit{h}\mathfrak{2}.\mathrm{w}</math>
    |           |   |   | m,
+
| width="10%" align="center"| <math>=\!</math>
    |           |  |   |
+
| width="25%" align="left" | <math>\mathfrak{2}.\mathit{h}\mathrm{w}</math>
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  =
+
| width="20%" | &nbsp;
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
|-
 +
| and in general;
 +
| align="right"  | <math>x,\!\mathfrak{2}.y</math>
 +
| align="center" | <math>=\!</math>
 +
| align="left"   | <math>\mathfrak{2}.x,\!y</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|}
  
o  +  o  o  o  o  +  m,n
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.75).</p>
B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
|}
  
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |    | 0 |
+
===Commentary Note 10.1===
| 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |    | 0 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  = | 0 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 | | 0 |    | 0 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 | | 0 |    | 0 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
  
Example 5Noble That Is Man
+
What Peirce is attempting to do in CP 3.75 is absolutely amazing and I personally did not see anything on par with it again until I began to study the application of mathematical category theory to computation and logic, back in the mid 1980'sTo completely evaluate the success of this attempt we would have to return to Peirce's earlier paper &ldquo;Upon the Logic of Mathematics&rdquo; (1867) to pick up some of the ideas about arithmetic that he set out there.
  
n,m =  "noble that is man"
+
Another branch of the investigation would require that we examine more carefully the entire syntactic mechanics of ''subjacent signs'' that Peirce uses to establish linkages among relational domains. It is important to note that these types of indices constitute a diacritical, interpretive, syntactic category under which Peirce also places the comma functor.
  
B  C  D  E  I   J  O
+
The way that I would currently approach both of these branches of the investigation would be to open up a wider context for the study of relational compositions, attempting to get at the essence of what is going on when we relate relations, possibly complex, to other relations, possibly simple.
o  +  o  o  +  +  +  m
 
    |  |              |
 
    |  |              |  n,
 
    |  |              |
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  =
 
  
o  +  o  o  o  o  +  n,m
+
===Commentary Note 10.2===
B  C  D  E  I  J  O
 
 
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |    | 0 |
 
| 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
| 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |    | 0 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 0 |  =  | 0 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |    | 0 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 | | 1 |    | 0 |
 
| 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 | | 1 |    | 1 |
 
</pre>
 
 
 
===Commentary Note 9.7===
 
 
 
<pre>
 
From this point forward we may think of idempotents, selectives,
 
and zero-one diagonal matrices as being roughly equivalent notions.
 
The only reason that I say "roughly" is that we are comparing ideas
 
at different levels of abstraction when we propose these connections.
 
 
 
We have covered the way that Peirce uses his invention of the
 
comma modifier to assimilate boolean multiplication, logical
 
conjunction, or what we may think of as "serial selection"
 
under his more general account of relative multiplication.
 
 
 
But the comma functor has its application to relative terms
 
of any arity, not just the zeroth arity of absolute terms,
 
and so there will be a lot more to explore on this point.
 
But now I must return to the anchorage of Peirce's text,
 
and hopefully get a chance to revisit this topic later.
 
</pre>
 
 
 
==Selection 10==
 
 
 
<pre>
 
| The Signs for Multiplication (cont.)
 
|
 
| The sum 'x' + 'x' generally denotes no logical term.
 
| But 'x',_oo + 'x',_oo may be considered as denoting
 
| some two 'x's.
 
|
 
| It is natural to write:
 
|
 
| 'x' + 'x'  =  !2!.'x'
 
|
 
| and
 
|
 
| 'x',_oo + 'x',_oo  = !2!.'x',_oo
 
|
 
| where the dot shows that this multiplication is invertible.
 
|
 
| We may also use the antique figures so that:
 
|
 
| !2!.'x',_oo  = `2`'x'
 
|
 
| just as
 
|
 
| !1!_oo  = `1`.
 
|
 
| Then `2` alone will denote some two things.
 
|
 
| But this multiplication is not in general commutative,
 
| and only becomes so when it affects a relative which
 
| imparts a relation such that a thing only bears it
 
| to 'one' thing, and one thing 'alone' bears it to
 
| a thing.
 
|
 
| For instance, the lovers of two women are not
 
| the same as two lovers of women, that is:
 
|
 
| 'l'`2`.w
 
|
 
| and
 
|
 
| `2`.'l'w
 
|
 
| are unequal;
 
|
 
| but the husbands of two women are the
 
| same as two husbands of women, that is:
 
|
 
| 'h'`2`.w  =  `2`.'h'w
 
|
 
| and in general:
 
|
 
| 'x',`2`.'y'  =  `2`.'x','y'.
 
|
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.75
 
|
 
| Charles Sanders Peirce,
 
|"Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives,
 
| Resulting from an Amplification of the Conceptions of Boole's Calculus of Logic",
 
|'Memoirs of the American Academy', Volume 9, pages 317-378, 26 January 1870,
 
|'Collected Papers' (CP 3.45-149), 'Chronological Edition' (CE 2, 359-429).
 
</pre>
 
  
===Commentary Note 10.1===
+
To say that a relative term &ldquo;imparts a relation&rdquo; is to say that it conveys information about the space of tuples in a cartesian product, that is, it determines a particular subset of that space.  When we study the combinations of relative terms, from the most elementary forms of composition to the most complex patterns of correlation, we are considering the ways that these constraints, determinations, and informations, as imparted by relative terms, can be compounded in the formation of syntax.
  
<pre>
+
Let us go back and look more carefully at just how it happens that Peirce's adjacent terms and subjacent indices manage to impart their respective measures of information about relations. I will begin with the two examples illustrated in Figures&nbsp;7 and 8, where I have drawn in the corresponding lines of identity between the subjacent marks of reference:  <math>\dagger, \ddagger, \parallel, \S, \P.\!</math>
What Peirce is attempting to do in CP 3.75 is absolutely amazing,
 
and I personally did not see anything on par with it again until
 
I began to study the application of mathematical category theory
 
to computation and logic, back in the mid 1980's.  To completely
 
evaluate the success of this attempt, we would have to return to
 
Peirce's earlier paper "Upon the Logic of Mathematics" (1867) to
 
pick up some of the ideas about arithmetic that he set out there.
 
  
Another branch of the investigation would require that we examine
+
<br>
more careully the entire syntactic mechanics of "subjacent signs"
 
that Peirce uses to establish linkages among relational domains.
 
It is important to note that these types of indices constitute
 
a diacritical, interpretive, syntactic category under which
 
Peirce also places the comma functor.
 
  
The way that I would currently approach both of these branches
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
of the investigation would be to open up a wider context for
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 7.0.jpg]] || (7)
the study of relational compositions, attempting to get at
+
|}
the essence of what is going on we when relate relations,
 
possibly complex, to other relations, possibly simple.
 
  
But that will take another cup of java ('c'j) ---
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
or maybe two, `2`'c'j = (!2!.'c',_oo)j ...
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 8.0.jpg]] || (8)
</pre>
+
|}
  
===Commentary Note 10.2===
+
One way to approach the problem of &ldquo;information fusion&rdquo; in Peirce's syntax is to soften the distinction between adjacent terms and subjacent signs and to treat the types of constraints that they separately signify more on a par with each other.  To that purpose, I will set forth a way of thinking about relational composition that emphasizes the set-theoretic constraints involved in the construction of a composite.
  
<pre>
+
For example, suppose that we are given the relations <math>L \subseteq X \times Y</math> and <math>M \subseteq Y \times Z.</math>  Table&nbsp;9 and Figure&nbsp;10 present two ways of picturing the constraints that are involved in constructing the relational composition <math>L \circ M \subseteq X \times Z.</math>
To say that a relative term "imparts a relation"
 
is to say that it conveys information about the
 
space of tuples in a cartesian product, that is,
 
it determines a particular subset of that space.
 
  
When we study the combinations of relative terms, from the most
+
<br>
elementary forms of composition to the most complex patterns of
 
correlation, we are considering the ways that these constraints,
 
determinations, and informations, as imparted by relative terms,
 
can be compounded in the formation of syntax.
 
  
Let us go back and look more carefully at just how it happens that
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
Peirce's jacent terms and subjacent indices manage to impart their
+
|+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 9.} ~~ \text{Relational Composition}\!</math>
respective measures of information about relations.
+
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | &nbsp;
 +
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
 +
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
 +
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>L\!</math>
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>M\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
| <math>Z\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>L \circ M\!</math>
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>Z\!</math>
 +
|}
  
I will begin with the two examples illustrated in Figures 1 and 2,
+
<br>
where I have drawn in the corresponding lines of identity between
 
the subjacent marks of reference #, $, %.
 
  
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
The way to read Table&nbsp;9 is to imagine that you are playing a game that involves placing tokens on the squares of a board that is marked in just this way.  The rules are that you have to place a single token on each marked square in the middle of the board in such a way that all of the indicated constraints are satisfied.  That is to say, you have to place a token whose denomination is a value in the set <math>X\!</math> on each of the squares marked <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} X {}^{\prime\prime},</math> and similarly for the squares marked <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} Y {}^{\prime\prime}</math> and <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} Z {}^{\prime\prime},</math> meanwhile leaving all of the blank squares empty.  Furthermore, the tokens placed in each row and column have to obey the relational constraints that are indicated at the heads of the corresponding row and column.  Thus, the two tokens from <math>X\!</math> have to denominate the very same value from <math>X,\!</math> and likewise for <math>Y\!</math> and <math>Z,\!</math> while the pairs of tokens on the rows marked <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} L {}^{\prime\prime}</math> and <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} M {}^{\prime\prime}</math> are required to denote elements that are in the relations <math>L\!</math> and <math>M,\!</math> respectivelyThe upshot is that when just this much is done, that is, when the <math>L,\!</math> <math>M,\!</math> and <math>\mathit{1}\!</math> relations are satisfied, then the row marked <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} L \circ M {}^{\prime\prime}</math> will automatically bear the tokens of a pair of elements in the composite relation <math>L \circ M.\!</math>
|                                                |
 
|                                                |
 
|        'l'__#      #'s'__$  $w                |
 
|            o      o    o  o                |
 
|              \     /       \ /                 |
 
|              \   /         o                  |
 
|                \ /         $                  |
 
|                o                              |
 
|                #                              |
 
|                                                |
 
|                                                |
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 1Lover of a Servant of a Woman
 
  
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
Figure&nbsp;10 shows a different way of viewing the same situation.
|                                                |
 
|                                                |
 
|        `g`__#__$    #'l'__%  %w  $h          |
 
|            o  o    o    o  o    o            |
 
|              \  \  /      \ /    /            |
 
|              \  \/        o    /              |
 
|                \ /\        %  /              |
 
|                o  ------o------                |
 
|                #        $                      |
 
|                                                |
 
|                                                |
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 2.  Giver of a Horse to a Lover of a Woman
 
  
One way to approach the problem of "information fusion"
+
<br>
in Peirce's syntax is to soften the distinction between
 
jacent terms and subjacent signs, and to treat the types
 
of constraints that they separately signify more on a par
 
with each other.
 
  
To that purpose, I will set forth a way of thinking about
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
relational composition that emphasizes the set-theoretic
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 10.jpg]] || (10)
constraints involved in the construction of a composite.
+
|}
  
For example, suppose that we are given the relations L c X x Y, M c Y x Z.
+
===Commentary Note 10.3===
Table 3 and Figure 4 present a couple of ways of picturing the constraints
 
that are involved in constructing the relational composition L o M c X x Z.
 
  
Table 3.  Relational Composition
+
I will devote some time to drawing out the relationships that exist among the different pictures of relations and relative terms that were shown above, or as redrawn here:
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|        #  !1!  |  !1!  |  !1!  |
 
o=========o=========o=========o=========o
 
|    L    #    X    |    Y    |        |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|    M    #        |    Y    |    Z    |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|  L o M  #    X    |        |    Z    |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
  
The way to read Table 3 is to imagine that you are
+
<br>
playing a game that involves placing tokens on the
 
squares of a board that is marked in just this way.
 
The rules are that you have to place a single token
 
on each marked square in the middle of the board in
 
such a way that all of the indicated constraints are
 
satisfied.  That is to say, you have to place a token
 
whose denomination is a value in the set X on each of
 
the squares marked "X", and similarly for the squares
 
marked "Y" and "Z", meanwhile leaving all of the blank
 
squares empty.  Furthermore, the tokens placed in each
 
row and column have to obey the relational constraints
 
that are indicated at the heads of the corresponding
 
row and column.  Thus, the two tokens from X have to
 
denominate the very same value from X, and likewise
 
for Y and Z, while the pairs of tokens on the rows
 
marked "L" and "M" are required to denote elements
 
that are in the relations L and M, respectively.
 
The upshot is that when just this much is done,
 
that is, when the L, M, and !1! relations are
 
satisfied, then the row marked "L o M" will
 
automatically bear the tokens of a pair of
 
elements in the composite relation L o M.
 
  
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
|                                                |
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 7.0.jpg]] || (11)
|               L    L o M    M                |
+
|}
|                @      @      @                |
 
|              / \    / \    / \              |
 
|              o  o  o  o  o  o              |
 
|             X  Y  X  Z  Y  Z              |
 
|             o  o  o  o  o  o              |
 
|              \  \ /    \ /  /              |
 
|                \  /      \  /                |
 
|                \ / \__ __/ \ /                |
 
|                  @    @    @                  |
 
|                !1!  !1!  !1!                |
 
|                                                |
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 4.  Relational Composition
 
  
Figure 4 merely shows a different way of viewing the same situation.
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
</pre>
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 8.0.jpg]] || (12)
 +
|}
  
===Commentary Note 10.3===
+
Figures&nbsp;11 and 12 present examples of relative multiplication in one of the styles of syntax that Peirce used, to which I added lines of identity to connect the corresponding marks of reference.  These pictures are adapted to showing the anatomy of relative terms, while the forms of analysis illustrated in Table&nbsp;13 and Figure&nbsp;14 are designed to highlight the structures of the objective relations themselves.
  
<pre>
+
<br>
I will devote some time to drawing out the relationships
 
that exist among the different pictures of relations and
 
relative terms that were shown above, or as redrawn here:
 
  
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
|                                                 |
+
|+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 13.} ~~ \text{Relational Composition}\!</math>
|                                                 |
+
|-
|       'l'__$      $'s'__%   %w                |
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | &nbsp;
|             o      o    o  o                |
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
|             \     /       \ /                 |
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
|               \   /         o                  |
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
|               \ /         %                  |
+
|-
|                 o                              |
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>L\!</math>
|                 $                              |
+
| <math>X\!</math>
|                                                 |
+
| <math>Y\!</math>
|                                                 |
+
| &nbsp;
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
|-
Figure 1.  Lover of a Servant of a Woman
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>S\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
| <math>Z\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>L \circ S\!</math>
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>Z\!</math>
 +
|}
  
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
<br>
|                                                |
 
|                                                |
 
|        `g`__$__%    $'l'__*  *w  %h          |
 
|            o  o    o    o  o    o            |
 
|              \  \  /      \ /    /            |
 
|              \  \/        o    /              |
 
|                \ /\        *  /              |
 
|                o  ------o------                |
 
|                $        %                      |
 
|                                                |
 
|                                                |
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 2.  Giver of a Horse to a Lover of a Woman
 
  
Table 3.  Relational Composition
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 14.jpg]] || (14)
|         #  !1!  |  !1!  |  !1!  |
+
|}
o=========o=========o=========o=========o
 
|   L    #    X    |    Y    |         |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|   S    #        |    Y    |    Z    |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|  L o S  #    X    |        |    Z    |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
  
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
There are many ways that Peirce might have gotten from his 1870 Notation for the Logic of Relatives to his more evolved systems of Logical GraphsIt is interesting to speculate on how the metamorphosis might have been accomplished by way of transformations that act on these nascent forms of syntax and that take place not too far from the pale of its means, that is, as nearly as possible according to the rules and the permissions of the initial system itself.
|                                                |
 
|                L    L o S    S                |
 
|                @      @      @                |
 
|              / \    / \    / \              |
 
|              o  o  o  o  o  o              |
 
|              X  Y  X  Z  Y  Z              |
 
|              o  o  o  o  o  o              |
 
|              \  \ /    \ /  /              |
 
|                \  /      \  /                |
 
|                \ / \__ __/ \ /                |
 
|                  @    @    @                  |
 
|                !1!  !1!  !1!                |
 
|                                                |
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 4Relational Composition
 
  
Figures 1 and 2 exhibit examples of relative multiplication
+
In Existential Graphs, a relation is represented by a node whose degree is the adicity of that relation, and which is adjacent via lines of identity to the nodes that represent its correlative relations, including as a special case any of its terminal individual arguments.
in one of Peirce's styles of syntax, to which I subtended
 
lines of identity to mark the anaphora of the correlates.
 
These pictures are adapted to showing the anatomy of the
 
relative terms, while the forms of analysis illustrated
 
in Table 3 and Figure 4 are designed to highlight the
 
structures of the objective relations themselves.
 
  
There are many ways that Peirce might have gotten from his 1870 Notation
+
In the 1870 Logic of Relatives, implicit lines of identity are invoked by the subjacent numbers and marks of reference only when a correlate of some relation is the relate of some relation.  Thus, the principal relate, which is not a correlate of any explicit relation, is not singled out in this way.
for the Logic of Relatives to his more evolved systems of Logical Graphs.
 
For my part, I find it interesting to speculate on how the metamorphosis
 
might have been accomplished by way of transformations that act on these
 
nascent forms of syntax and that take place not too far from the pale of
 
its means, that is, as nearly as possible according to the rules and the
 
permissions of the initial system itself.
 
  
In Existential Graphs, a relation is represented by a node
+
Remarkably enough, the comma modifier itself provides us with a mechanism to abstract the logic of relations from the logic of relatives, and thus to forge a possible link between the syntax of relative terms and the more graphical depiction of the objective relations themselves.
whose degree is the adicity of that relation, and which is
 
adjacent via lines of identity to the nodes that represent
 
its correlative relations, including as a special case any
 
of its terminal individual arguments.
 
  
In the 1870 Logic of Relatives, implicit lines of identity are invoked by
+
Figure&nbsp;15 demonstrates this possibility, posing a transitional case between the style of syntax in Figure&nbsp;11 and the picture of composition in Figure&nbsp;14.
the subjacent numbers and marks of reference only when a correlate of some
 
relation is the relate of some relation.  Thus, the principal relate, which
 
is not a correlate of any explicit relation, is not singled out in this way.
 
  
Remarkably enough, the comma modifier itself provides us with a mechanism
+
<br>
to abstract the logic of relations from the logic of relatives, and thus
 
to forge a possible link between the syntax of relative terms and the
 
more graphical depiction of the objective relations themselves.
 
  
Figure 5 demonstrates this possibility, posing a transitional case between
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
the style of syntax in Figure 1 and the picture of composition in Figure 4.
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 15.jpg]] || (15)
 +
|}
  
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
+
In this composite sketch the diagonal extension <math>\mathit{1}\!</math> of the universe <math>\mathbf{1}\!</math> is invoked up front to anchor an explicit line of identity for the leading relate of the composition, while the terminal argument <math>\mathrm{w}\!</math> has been generalized to the whole universe <math>\mathbf{1},\!</math> in effect, executing an act of abstraction.  This type of universal bracketing isolates the composing of the relations <math>L\!</math> and <math>S\!</math> to form the composite <math>L \circ S.\!</math>  The three relational domains <math>X, Y, Z\!</math> may be distinguished from one another, or else rolled up into a single universe of discourse, as one prefers.
|                                                          |
 
|                          L o S                          |
 
|                ____________@____________                |
 
|                /                        \                |
 
|              /      L            S      \              |
 
|              /      @            @      \              |
 
|            /      / \          / \      \            |
 
|            /      /  \        /  \      \            |
 
|          o      o    o      o    o      o          |
 
|          X      X    Y      Y    Z      Z          |
 
|      1,__#      #'l'__$      $'s'__%      %1          |
 
|          o      o    o      o    o      o          |
 
|            \    /      \    /      \    /            |
 
|            \  /        \  /        \  /            |
 
|              \ /          \ /          \ /              |
 
|              @            @            @              |
 
|              !1!          !1!          !1!              |
 
|                                                          |
 
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 5.  Anything that is a Lover of a Servant of Anything
 
 
 
In this composite sketch, the diagonal extension of the universe 1
 
is invoked up front to anchor an explicit line of identity for the
 
leading relate of the composition, while the terminal argument "w"
 
has been generalized to the whole universe 1, in effect, executing
 
an act of abstraction.  This type of universal bracketing isolates
 
the composing of the relations L and S to form the composite L o S.
 
The three relational domains X, Y, Z may be distinguished from one
 
another, or else rolled up into a single universe of discourse, as
 
one prefers.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 10.4===
 
===Commentary Note 10.4===
  
<pre>
+
From now on I will use the forms of analysis exemplified in the last set of Figures and Tables as a routine bridge between the logic of relative terms and the logic of their extended relations.  For future reference, we may think of Table&nbsp;13 as illustrating the ''spreadsheet'' model of relational composition, while Figure&nbsp;14 may be thought of as making a start toward a ''hypergraph'' model of generalized compositions. I will explain the hypergraph model in some detail at a later point. The transitional form of analysis represented by Figure&nbsp;15 may be called the ''universal bracketing'' of relatives as relations.
From now on I will use the forms of analysis exemplified in the last set of
 
Figures and Tables as a routine bridge between the logic of relative terms
 
and the logic of their extended relations.  For future reference, we may
 
think of Table 3 as illustrating the "solitaire" or "spreadsheet" model
 
of relational composition, while Figure 4 may be thought of as making
 
a start toward the "hyper(di)graph" model of generalized compositions.
 
I will explain the hypergraph model in some detail at a later point.
 
The transitional form of analysis represented by Figure 5 may be
 
called the "universal bracketing" of relatives as relations.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 10.5===
 
===Commentary Note 10.5===
  
<pre>
+
We have sufficiently covered the application of the comma functor, or the diagonal extension, to absolute terms, so let us return to where we were in working our way through CP&nbsp;3.73 and see whether we can validate Peirce's statements about the &ldquo;commifications&rdquo; of 2-adic relative terms that yield their 3-adic diagonal extensions.
We have sufficiently covered the application of the comma functor,
 
or the diagonal extension, to absolute terms, so let us return to
 
where we were in working our way through CP 3.73, and see whether
 
we can validate Peirce's statements about the "commifications" of
 
2-adic relative terms that yield their 3-adic diagonal extensions.
 
  
| But not only may any absolute term be thus regarded as
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
| a relative term, but any relative term may in the same
 
| way be regarded as a relative with one correlate more.
 
| It is convenient to take this additional correlate as
 
| the first one.
 
 
|
 
|
| Then:
+
<p>But not only may any absolute term be thus regarded as a relative term, but any relative term may in the same way be regarded as a relative with one correlate more.  It is convenient to take this additional correlate as the first one.</p>
 +
 
 +
<p>Then:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w}</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| 'l','s'w
+
<p>will denote a lover of a woman that is a servant of that woman.</p>
|
+
 
| will denote a lover of a woman
+
<p>The comma here after <math>\mathit{l}\!</math> should not be considered as altering at all the meaning of <math>\mathit{l}\!</math>, but as only a subjacent sign, serving to alter the arrangement of the correlates.</p>
| that is a servant of that woman.
 
|
 
| The comma here after 'l' should not be considered
 
| as altering at all the meaning of 'l', but as only
 
| a subjacent sign, serving to alter the arrangement
 
| of the correlates.
 
|
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.73
 
  
Just to plant our feet on a more solid stage,
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.73).</p>
let's apply this idea to the Othello example.
+
|}
  
For this performance only, just to make the example more interesting,
+
Just to plant our feet on a more solid stage, let's apply this idea to the Othello example.  For this performance only, just to make the example more interesting, let us assume that <math>\mathrm{Jeste ~ (J)}\!</math> is secretly in love with <math>\mathrm{Desdemona ~ (D)}.\!</math>
let us assume that Jeste (J) is secretly in love with Desdemona (D).
 
  
 
Then we begin with the modified data set:
 
Then we begin with the modified data set:
  
= "woman"           = B +, D +, E
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
+
|
'l'  =  "lover of ---"    = B:C +, C:B +, D:O +, E:I +, I:E +, J:D +, O:D
+
<math>\begin{array}{*{15}{c}}
 
+
\mathrm{w}
's= "servant of ---"  =  C:O +, E:D +, I:O +, J:D +, J:O
+
& =      & \mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathit{l}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{E}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{D}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathit{s}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
And next we derive the following results:
 
And next we derive the following results:
  
'l', = "lover that is --- of ---"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
+
|
      =  B:B:C +, C:C:B +, D:D:O +, E:E:I +, I:I:E +, J:J:D +, O:O:D
+
<math>\begin{array}{l}
 
+
\mathit{l}, ~=
'l','s'w = (B:B:C +, C:C:B +, D:D:O +, E:E:I +, I:I:E +, J:J:D +, O:O:D)
+
\\[6pt]
 
+
\text{lover that is}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\, \text{of}\, \underline{~~ ~~} ~=
          x  (C:O +, E:D +, I:O +, J:D +, J:O)
+
\\[6pt]
 
+
(\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{D})
          x  (B +, D +, E)
+
\\[12pt]
 +
\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w} ~=
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
(\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{D})
 +
\\
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{O} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{O})
 +
\\
 +
\times
 +
\\
 +
(\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E})
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
Now what are we to make of that?
 
Now what are we to make of that?
  
If we operate in accordance with Peirce's example of `g`'o'h
+
If we operate in accordance with Peirce's example of <math>\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}</math> as the &ldquo;giver of a horse to an owner of that horse&rdquo;, then we may assume that the associative law and the distributive law are in force, allowing us to derive this equation:
as the "giver of a horse to an owner of that horse", then we
 
may assume that the associative law and the distributive law
 
are by default in force, allowing us to derive this equation:
 
  
'l','s'w = 'l','s'(B +, D +, E)
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w}
 +
& = &
 +
\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}(\mathrm{B} ~~+\!\!,~~ \mathrm{D} ~~+\!\!,~~ \mathrm{E})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{B} ~~+\!\!,~~ \mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{D} ~~+\!\!,~~ \mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{E}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
          =  'l','s'B +, 'l','s'D +, 'l','s'E
+
Evidently what Peirce means by the associative principle, as it applies to this type of product, is that a product of elementary relatives having the form <math>(\mathrm{R}\!:\!\mathrm{S}\!:\!\mathrm{T})(\mathrm{S}\!:\!\mathrm{T})(\mathrm{T})\!</math> is equal to <math>\mathrm{R}\!</math> but that no other form of product yields a non-null result.  Scanning the implied terms of the triple product tells us that only the case <math>(\mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D})(\mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{D})(\mathrm{D}) = \mathrm{J}\!</math> is non-null.
  
Evidently what Peirce means by the associative principle,
+
It follows that:
as it applies to this type of product, is that a product
 
of elementary relatives having the form (R:S:T)(S:T)(T)
 
is equal to R but that no other form of product yields
 
a non-null result.  Scanning the implied terms of the
 
triple product tells us that only the following case
 
is non-null:  J = (J:J:D)(J:D)(D).  It follows that:
 
  
'l','s'w = "lover and servant of a woman"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
+
|
          = "lover that is a servant of a woman"
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 
+
\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w}
          = "lover of a woman that is a servant of that woman"
+
& = &
 
+
\text{lover and servant of a woman}
          = J
+
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\text{lover that is a servant of a woman}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\text{lover of a woman that is a servant of that woman}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{J}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
And so what Peirce says makes sense in this case.
 
And so what Peirce says makes sense in this case.
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 10.6===
 
===Commentary Note 10.6===
  
<pre>
+
As Peirce observes, it is not possible to work with relations in general without eventually abandoning all of one's algebraic principles, in due time the associative law and maybe even the distributive law, just as we already gave up the commutative law. It cannot be helped, as we cannot reflect on a law if not from a perspective outside it, at any rate, virtually so.
As Peirce observes, it is not possible to work with
 
relations in general without eventually abandoning
 
all of one's algebraic principles, in due time the
 
associative and maybe even the distributive, just
 
as we have already left behind the commutative.
 
It cannot be helped, as we cannot reflect on
 
a law if not from a perspective outside it,
 
that is to say, at any rate, virtually so.
 
  
One way to do this would be from the standpoint of the combinator calculus,
+
This could be done from the standpoint of the combinator calculus, and there are places where Peirce verges on systems that are very similar, but here we are making a deliberate effort to stay within the syntactic neighborhood of Peirce's 1870 Logic of Relatives. Not too coincidentally, it is for the sake of making smoother transitions between narrower and wider regimes of algebraic law that we have been developing the paradigm of Figures and Tables indicated above.
and there are places where Peirce verges on systems that are very similar,
 
but I am making a deliberate effort to remain here as close as possible
 
within the syntactoplastic chronism of his 1870 Logic of Relatives.
 
So let us make use of the smoother transitions that are afforded
 
by the paradigmatic Figures and Tables that I drew up earlier.
 
  
For the next few episodes, then, I will examine the examples
+
For the next few episodes, then, I will examine the examples that Peirce gives at the next level of complication in the multiplication of relative terms, for example, the three that are repeated below.
that Peirce gives at the next level of complication in the
 
multiplication of relative terms, for instance, the three
 
that I have redrawn below.
 
  
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
|                                                |
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 8.0.jpg]] || (16)
|                                                 |
+
|}
|        `g`__$__%    $'l'__*  *w  %h          |
 
|              o  o    o    o  o    o          |
 
|              \  \  /      \ /    /            |
 
|                \  \/        @    /            |
 
|                \ /\______ ______/              |
 
|                 @        @                    |
 
|                                                 |
 
|                                                |
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 6.  Giver of a Horse to a Lover of a Woman
 
  
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
|                                                |
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 17.0.jpg]] || (17)
|                                                 |
+
|}
|        `g`__$__%    $'o'__*  *%h              |
 
|              o  o    o    o  oo              |
 
|              \  \  /      \ //                |
 
|                \  \/        @/                |
 
|                \ /\____ ____/                  |
 
|                 @      @                      |
 
|                                                 |
 
|                                                |
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 7.  Giver of a Horse to an Owner of It
 
  
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
|                                                |
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 18.jpg]] || (18)
|                                                 |
+
|}
|        'l',__$__%    $'s'__*  *%w              |
 
|              o  o    o    o  oo              |
 
|              \  \  /      \ //                |
 
|                \  \/        @/                |
 
|                \ /\____ ____/                  |
 
|                 @      @                      |
 
|                                                 |
 
|                                                |
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 8.  Lover that is a Servant of a Woman
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 10.7===
 
===Commentary Note 10.7===
  
<pre>
+
Here is what I get when I try to analyze Peirce's &ldquo;giver of a horse to a lover of a woman&rdquo; example along the same lines as the dyadic compositions.
Here is what I get when I try to analyze Peirce's
+
 
"giver of a horse to a lover of a woman" example
+
We may begin with the mark-up shown in Figure&nbsp;19.
along the same lines as the 2-adic compositions.
+
 
 +
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 8.0.jpg]] || (19)
 +
|}
  
We may begin with the mark-up shown in Figure 6.
+
If we analyze this in accord with the spreadsheet model of relational composition, the core of it is a particular way of composing a triadic ''giving'' relation <math>G \subseteq T \times U \times V\!</math> with a dyadic ''loving'' relation <math>L \subseteq U \times W\!</math> so as to obtain a specialized sort of triadic relation <math>(G \circ L) \subseteq T \times V \times W.\!</math>  The applicable constraints on tuples are shown in Table&nbsp;20.
  
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
<br>
|                                                |
 
|                                                |
 
|        `g`__$__%    $'l'__*  *w  %h          |
 
|              o  o    o    o  o    o          |
 
|              \  \  /      \ /    /            |
 
|                \  \/        @    /            |
 
|                \ /\______ ______/              |
 
|                  @        @                    |
 
|                                                |
 
|                                                |
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 6.  Giver of a Horse to a Lover of a Woman
 
  
If we analyze this in accord with the "spreadsheet" model
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:75%"
of relational composition, the core of it is a particular
+
|+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 20.} ~~ \text{Composite of Triadic and Dyadic Relations}\!</math>
way of composing a 3-adic "giving" relation G c T x U x V
+
|-
with a 2-adic "loving" relation L c U x W so as to obtain
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; width:20%" | &nbsp;
a specialized sort of 3-adic relation (G o L) c T x W x V.
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:20%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
The applicable constraints on tuples are shown in Table 9.
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:20%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
 +
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:20%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
 +
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:20%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>G\!</math>
 +
| <math>T\!</math>
 +
| <math>U\!</math>
 +
| <math>V\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>L\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>U\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>W\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>G \circ L</math>
 +
| <math>T\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>V\!</math>
 +
| <math>W\!</math>
 +
|}
  
Table 9.  Composite of Triadic and Dyadic Relations
+
<br>
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|        #  !1!  |  !1!  |  !1!  |  !1!  |
 
o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o
 
|    G    #    T    |    U    |        |    V    |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|    L    #        |    U    |    W    |        |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|  G o L  #    T    |        |    W    |    V    |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
  
The hypergraph picture of the abstract composition is given in Figure 10.
+
The hypergraph picture of the abstract composition is given in Figure&nbsp;21.
  
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
|                                                                    |
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 21.jpg]] || (21)
|                               G o L                                |
+
|}
|                      ___________@___________                      |
 
|                     /                  \    \                      |
 
|                     /  G              L  \    \                    |
 
|                    /  @              @  \    \                    |
 
|                  /  /|\            / \  \    \                  |
 
|                  /  / | \          /  \  \    \                  |
 
|                /  /  |  \        /    \  \    \                |
 
|                /  /  |  \      /      \  \    \                |
 
|              o  o    o    o    o        o  o    o              |
 
|              T  T    U    V    U        W  W    V              |
 
|            1,_#  #`g`_$____%    $'l'______*  *1  %1              |
 
|              o  o    o    o    o        o  o    o              |
 
|                \ /      \    \  /          \ /    /                |
 
|                @        \    \/            @    /                |
 
|                !1!        \  /\            !1!  /                  |
 
|                            \ /  \_______ _______/                  |
 
|                            @          @                          |
 
|                            !1!        !1!                          |
 
|                                                                    |
 
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 10.  Anything that is a Giver of Anything to a Lover of Anything
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 10.8===
 
===Commentary Note 10.8===
  
<pre>
+
There's a critical transition point in sight of Peirce's 1870 Logic of Relatives and it's a point that turns on the teridentity relation.
In taking up the next example of relational composition,
 
let's exchange the relation 't' = "trainer of ---" for
 
Peirce's relation 'o' = "owner of ---", simply for the
 
sake of avoiding conflicts in the symbols that we use.
 
In this way, Figure 7 is transformed into Figure 11.
 
  
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
In taking up the next example of relational composition, let's substitute the relation <math>\mathit{t} = \text{taker of}\, \underline{~~ ~~}\!</math> for Peirce's relation <math>\mathit{o} = \text{owner of}\, \underline{~~ ~~},\!</math> simply for the sake of avoiding conflicts in the symbols we use.  In this way, Figure&nbsp;17 is transformed into Figure&nbsp;22.
|                                                |
 
|                                                |
 
|        `g`__$__%    $'t'__*  *%h              |
 
|              o  o    o    o  oo              |
 
|              \ \ /       \ //                |
 
|                \ \/        @/                |
 
|                \ /\____ ____/                 |
 
|                  @      @                      |
 
|                                                |
 
|                                                |
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 11. Giver of a Horse to a Trainer of It
 
  
Now here's an interesting point, in fact, a critical transition point,
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
that we see resting in potential but a stone's throw removed from the
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 22.jpg]] || (22)
chronism, the secular neigborhood, the temporal vicinity of Peirce's
+
|}
1870 LOR, and it's a vertex that turns on the teridentity relation.
 
  
The hypergraph picture of the abstract composition is given in Figure 12.
+
The hypergraph picture of the abstract composition is given in Figure&nbsp;23.
  
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
|                                                                    |
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 23.jpg]] || (23)
|                               G o T                                |
+
|}
|                _________________@_________________                |
 
|                /                                  \                |
 
|              /        G              T            \              |
 
|              /        @              @              \              |
 
|            /        /|\            / \              \            |
 
|            /        / | \          /  \              \            |
 
|          /        /  |  \        /    \              \          |
 
|          /        /  |  \      /      \              \          |
 
|        o        o    o    o    o        o              o        |
 
|        X        X    Y    Z    Y        Z              Z        |
 
|      1,_#        #`g`_$____%    $'t'______%              %1        |
 
|        o        o    o    o    o        o              o        |
 
|         \      /      \    \  /          |            /          |
 
|           \    /        \    \/          |            /          |
 
|            \  /          \  /\          |          /            |
 
|            \ /            \ /  \__________|__________/            |
 
|              @              @              @                        |
 
|            !1!            !1!            !1!                      |
 
|                                                                    |
 
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 12.  Anything that is a Giver of Anything to a Trainer of It
 
  
If we analyze this in accord with the "spreadsheet" model
+
If we analyze this in accord with the spreadsheet model of relational composition, the core of it is a particular way of composing a triadic &ldquo;giving&rdquo; relation <math>G \subseteq X \times Y \times Z\!</math> with a dyadic &ldquo;taking&rdquo; relation <math>T \subseteq Y \times Z\!</math> in such a way as to determine a certain dyadic relation <math>(G \circ T) \subseteq X \times Z.\!</math>  Table&nbsp;24 schematizes the associated constraints on tuples.
of relational composition, the core of it is a particular
 
way of composing a 3-adic "giving" relation G c X x Y x Z
 
with a 2-adic "training" relation T c Y x Z in such a way
 
as to determine a certain 2-adic relation (G o T) c X x Z.
 
Table 13 schematizes the associated constraints on tuples.
 
  
Table 13.  Another Brand of Composition
+
<br>
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|        #  !1!  |  !1!  |  !1!  |
 
o=========o=========o=========o=========o
 
|    G    #    X    |    Y    |    Z    |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|    T    #        |    Y    |    Z    |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|  G o T  #    X    |        |    Z    |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
  
So we see that the notorious teridentity relation,
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
which I have left equivocally denoted by the same
+
|+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 24.} ~~ \text{Another Brand of Composition}\!</math>
symbol as the identity relation !1!, is already
+
|-
implicit in Peirce's discussion at this point.
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | &nbsp;
</pre>
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
 +
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
 +
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>G\!</math>
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
| <math>Z\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>T\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
| <math>Z\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>G \circ T</math>
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>Z\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
<br>
 +
 
 +
So we see that the notorious teridentity relation, which I have left equivocally denoted by the same symbol as the identity relation <math>\mathit{1},\!</math> is already implicit in Peirce's discussion at this point.
  
 
===Commentary Note 10.9===
 
===Commentary Note 10.9===
  
<pre>
+
The use of the concepts of identity and teridentity is not to identify a thing-in-itself with itself, much less twice or thrice over &mdash; there is no need and therefore no utility in that.  I&nbsp;can imagine Peirce asking, on Kantian principles if not entirely on Kantian premisses, <i>Where is the manifold to be unified?</i> The manifold that demands unification does not reside in the object but in the phenomena, that is, in the appearances that might have been appearances of different objects but that happen to be constrained by these identities to being just so many aspects, facets, parts, roles, or signs of one and the same object.
The use of the concepts of identity and teridentity is not to identify
 
a thing in itself with itself, much less twice or thrice over, since
 
there is no need and thus no utility in that.  I can imagine Peirce
 
asking, on Kantian principles if not entirely on Kantian premisses,
 
"Where is the manifold to be unified?" The manifold that demands
 
unification does not reside in the object but in the phenomena,
 
that is, in the appearances that might have been appearances
 
of different objects but that happen to be constrained by
 
these identities to being just so many aspects, facets,
 
parts, roles, or signs of one and the same object.
 
  
For example, notice how the various identity concepts actually
+
For example, notice how the various identity concepts actually functioned in the last example, where they had the opportunity to show their behavior in something like their natural habitat.
functioned in the last example, where they had the opportunity
 
to show their behavior in something like their natural habitat.
 
  
The use of the teridentity concept in the case
+
The use of the teridentity concept in the case of the &ldquo;giver of a horse to a taker of it&rdquo; is to say that the thing appearing with respect to its quality under an absolute term, <i>a&nbsp;horse</i>, the thing appearing with respect to its existence as the correlate of a dyadic relative, <i>a&nbsp;potential possession</i>, and the thing appearing with respect to its synthesis as the correlate of a triadic relative, <i>a&nbsp;gift</i>, are one and the same thing.
of the "giver of a horse to a trainer of it" is
 
to stipulate that the thing appearing with respect
 
to its quality under the aspect of an absolute term,
 
a horse, and the thing appearing with respect to its
 
recalcitrance in the role of the correlate of a 2-adic
 
relative, a brute to be trained, and the thing appearing
 
with respect to its synthesis in the role of a correlate
 
of a 3-adic relative, a gift, are one and the same thing.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 10.10===
 
===Commentary Note 10.10===
  
<pre>
+
The last of the three examples involving the composition of triadic relatives with dyadic relatives is shown again in Figure&nbsp;25.
Figure 8 depicts the last of the three examples involving
 
the composition of 3-adic relatives with 2-adic relatives:
 
  
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
|                                                |
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 18.jpg]] || (25)
|                                                 |
+
|}
|       'l',__$__%    $'s'__*  *%w              |
 
|             o  o    o    o  oo              |
 
|              \  \  /      \ //                |
 
|                \  \/        @/                |
 
|                \ /\____ ____/                  |
 
|                  @      @                      |
 
|                                                |
 
|                                                |
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 8.  Lover that is a Servant of a Woman
 
  
The hypergraph picture of the abstract composition is given in Figure 14.
+
The hypergraph picture of the abstract composition is given in Figure&nbsp;26.
  
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
|                                                                    |
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 26.jpg]] || (26)
|                               L , S                                |
+
|}
|                __________________^__________________                |
 
|              /                                    \              |
 
|              /      L_,              S              \              |
 
|            /        @              @              \            |
 
|            /        /|\            / \              \            |
 
|          /        / | \          /  \              \          |
 
|          /        /  |  \        /    \              \          |
 
|        /        /  |  \      /      \              \        |
 
|        /        /    |    \    /        \              \        |
 
|      o        o    o    o  o          o              o      |
 
|      X        X    X    Y  X          Y              Y      |
 
|   1,_#        #'l',_$_____%  $'t'________%              %1      |
 
|       o        o    o    o  o          o              o      |
 
|        \      /      \    \ /            |              /        |
 
|        \    /        \    \            |            /        |
 
|          \  /          \  / \            |            /          |
 
|          \ /            \ /  \___________|___________/          |
 
|            @              @                @                      |
 
|          !1!            !1!              !1!                      |
 
|                                                                    |
 
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 14.  Anything that's a Lover of Anything and that's a Servant of It
 
  
This example illustrates the way that Peirce analyzes the logical conjunction,
+
This example illustrates the way that Peirce analyzes the logical conjunction, we might even say the ''parallel conjunction'', of a pair of dyadic relatives in terms of the comma extension and the same style of composition that we saw in the last example, that is, according to a pattern of anaphora that invokes the teridentity relation.
we might even say the "parallel conjunction", of a couple of 2-adic relatives
 
in terms of the comma extension and the same style of composition that we saw
 
in the last example, that is, according to a pattern of anaphora that invokes
 
the teridentity relation.
 
  
If we lay out this analysis of conjunction on the spreadsheet model
+
If we lay out this analysis of conjunction on the spreadsheet model of relational composition, the gist of it is the diagonal extension of a dyadic ''loving'' relation <math>L \subseteq X \times Y\!</math> to the corresponding triadic ''being and loving'' relation <math>L \subseteq X \times X \times Y,\!</math> which is then composed in a specific way with a dyadic ''serving'' relation <math>S \subseteq X \times Y\!</math> so as to determine the dyadic relation <math>L,\!S \subseteq X \times Y.\!</math> Table&nbsp;27 schematizes the associated constraints on tuples.
of relational composition, the gist of it is the diagonal extension
 
of a 2-adic "loving" relation L c X x Y to the corresponding 3-adic
 
"loving and being" relation L_, c X x X x Y, which is then composed
 
in a specific way with a 2-adic "serving" relation S c X x Y, so as
 
to determine the 2-adic relation L,S c X x Y.  Table 15 schematizes
 
the associated constraints on tuples.
 
  
Table 15. Conjunction Via Composition
+
<br>
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
 
|         #  !1!   |   !1!   |   !1!   |
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
o=========o=========o=========o=========o
+
|+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 27.} ~~ \text{Conjunction Via Composition}\!</math>
|   L,   #    X   |   X   |   Y   |
+
|-
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | &nbsp;
|   S    #        |   X   |   Y   |
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
| L , S #    X   |         |   Y   |
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
|-
</pre>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>L,\!</math>
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>S\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>L,\!S</math>
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
<br>
  
 
===Commentary Note 10.11===
 
===Commentary Note 10.11===
  
<pre>
+
Let us return to the point where we left off unpacking the contents of CP&nbsp;3.73. Peirce remarks that the comma operator can be iterated at will:
I return to where we were in unpacking the contents of CP 3.73.
 
Peirce remarks that the comma operator can be iterated at will:
 
  
| In point of fact, since a comma may be added in this way to any
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
| relative term, it may be added to one of these very relatives
 
| formed by a comma, and thus by the addition of two commas
 
| an absolute term becomes a relative of two correlates.
 
 
|
 
|
| So:
+
<p>In point of fact, since a comma may be added in this way to any relative term, it may be added to one of these very relatives formed by a comma, and thus by the addition of two commas an absolute term becomes a relative of two correlates.</p>
 +
 
 +
<p>So:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{m},\!,\!\mathrm{b},\!\mathrm{r}</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| m,,b,r
+
<p>interpreted like</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| interpreted like
+
<p>means a man that is a rich individual and is a black that is that rich individual.</p>
 +
 
 +
<p>But this has no other meaning than:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{m},\!\mathrm{b},\!\mathrm{r}</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| `g`'o'h
+
<p>or a man that is a black that is rich.</p>
|
 
| means a man that is a rich individual and
 
| is a black that is that rich individual.
 
|
 
| But this has no other meaning than:
 
|
 
| m,b,r
 
|
 
| or a man that is a black that is rich.
 
|
 
| Thus we see that, after one comma is added, the
 
| addition of another does not change the meaning
 
| at all, so that whatever has one comma after it
 
| must be regarded as having an infinite number.
 
|
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.73
 
  
Again, let us check whether this makes sense
+
<p>Thus we see that, after one comma is added, the addition of another does not change the meaning at all, so that whatever has one comma after it must be regarded as having an infinite number.</p>
on the stage of our small but dramatic model.
 
  
Let's say that Desdemona and Othello are rich,
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.73).</p>
and, among the persons of the play, only they.
+
|}
  
With this premiss we obtain a sample of absolute terms
+
Again, let us check whether this makes sense on the stage of our small but dramatic model.  Let's say that Desdemona and Othello are rich, and, among the persons of the play, only they.  With this premiss we obtain a sample of absolute terms that is sufficiently ample to work through our example:
that is sufficiently ample to work through our example:
 
  
1   =   B +, C +, D +, E +, I +, J +, O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{15}{c}}
 +
\mathbf{1}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{b}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{m}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{r}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
b    =  O
+
One application of the comma operator yields the following 2-adic relatives:
  
m   =   C +, I +, J +, O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{15}{c}}
 +
\mathbf{1,}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{E}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{b,}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{m,}
 +
& =     & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{r,}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
r    =  D +, O
+
Another application of the comma operator generates the following 3-adic relatives:
  
One application of the comma operator
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
yields the following 2-adic relatives:
+
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{9}{c}}
 +
\mathbf{1,\!,}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{E}
 +
\\
 +
&        &
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{b,\!,}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{m,\!,}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{r,\!,}
 +
& =      & \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D}
 +
& +\!\!, & \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
1,   =  B:B +, C:C +, D:D +, E:E +, I:I +, J:J +, O:O
+
Assuming the associativity of multiplication among 2-adic relatives, we may compute the product <math>~\mathrm{m},\mathrm{b},\mathrm{r}~</math> by a brute force method as follows:
  
b,   =   O:O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathrm{m},\mathrm{b},\mathrm{r}
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O})(\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O})(\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O})(\mathrm{O})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
m,   =  C:C +, I:I +, J:J +, O:O
+
This says that a man that is black that is rich is Othello, which is true on the premisses of our present universe of discourse.
  
r,   =  D:D +, O:O
+
Following the standard associative combinations of <math>\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h},</math> the product <math>~\mathrm{m},\!,\mathrm{b},\mathrm{r}~</math> is multiplied out along the following lines, where the trinomials of the form <math>\mathrm{(X\!:\!Y\!:\!Z)(Y\!:\!Z)(Z)}\!</math> are the only ones that produce a non-null result, namely, <math>\mathrm{(X\!:\!Y\!:\!Z)(Y\!:\!Z)(Z) = X}.\!</math>
  
Another application of the comma operator
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
generates the following 3-adic relatives:
+
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
\mathrm{m},\!,\mathrm{b},\mathrm{r}
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O})(\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O})(\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
(\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O})(\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O})(\mathrm{O})
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
1,, =   B:B:B +, C:C:C +, D:D:D +, E:E:E +, I:I:I +, J:J:J +, O:O:O
+
So we have that <math>\mathrm{m},\!,\mathrm{b},\mathrm{r} ~=~ \mathrm{m},\mathrm{b},\mathrm{r}.</math>
  
b,, =  O:O:O
+
In closing, observe that the teridentity relation has turned up again in this context, as the second comma-ing of the universal term itself:
  
m,, =   C:C:C +, I:I:I +, J:J:J +, O:O:O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{l}
 +
\mathbf{1},\!, ~=~
 +
\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D}\!:\!\mathrm{D} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{E}\!:\!\mathrm{E} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I}\!:\!\mathrm{I} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J}\!:\!\mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}\!:\!\mathrm{O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
r,,  =   D:D:D +, O:O:O
+
===Commentary Note 10.12===
  
Assuming the associativity of multiplication among 2-adic relatives,
+
Potential ambiguities in Peirce's two versions of the &ldquo;rich black man&rdquo; example can be resolved by providing them with explicit graphical markups, as shown in Figures&nbsp;28&nbsp;and&nbsp;29.
we may compute the product m,b,r by a brute force method as follows:
 
  
m,b,r  = (C:C +, I:I +, J:J +, O:O)(O:O)(D +, O)
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 28.jpg]] || (28)
 +
|-
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 29.jpg]] || (29)
 +
|}
  
      =  (C:C +, I:I +, J:J +, O:O)(O)
+
On the other hand, as the forms of relational composition become more complex, the corresponding algebraic products of elementary relatives, for example, <math>\mathrm{(x\!:\!y\!:\!z)(y\!:\!z)(z)},\!</math> will not always determine unique results without the addition of more information about the intended linking of terms.
  
      = O
+
==Selection 11==
  
This avers that a man that is black that is rich is Othello,
+
===The Signs for Multiplication (concl.)===
which is true on the premisses of our universe of discourse.
 
  
The stock associations of `g`'o'h lead us to multiply out the
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
product m,,b,r along the following lines, where the trinomials
+
|
of the form (X:Y:Z)(Y:Z)(Z) are the only ones that produce any
+
<p>The conception of multiplication we have adopted is that of the application of one relation to another.  So, a quaternion being the relation of one vector to another, the multiplication of quaternions is the application of one such relation to a second.</p>
non-null result, specifically, of the form (X:Y:Z)(Y:Z)(Z) = X.
 
  
m,,b,r  =  (C:C:C +, I:I:I +, J:J:J +, O:O:O)(O:O)(D +, O)
+
<p>Even ordinary numerical multiplication involves the same idea, for <math>~2 \times 3~</math> is a pair of triplets, and <math>~3 \times 2~</math> is a triplet of pairs, where "triplet of" and "pair of" are evidently relatives.</p>
  
        =  (O:O:O)(O:O)(O)
+
<p>If we have an equation of the form:</p>
 
+
|-
        =  O
+
| align="center" | <math>xy ~=~ z</math>
 
+
|-
So we have that m,,b,r = m,b,r.
 
 
 
In closing, observe that the teridentity relation has turned up again
 
in this context, as the second comma-ing of the universal term itself:
 
 
 
1,,  =  B:B:B +, C:C:C +, D:D:D +, E:E:E +, I:I:I +, J:J:J +, O:O:O.
 
</pre>
 
 
 
==Selection 11==
 
 
 
<pre>
 
| The Signs for Multiplication (concl.)
 
 
|
 
|
| The conception of multiplication we have adopted is that of
+
<p>and there are just as many <math>x\!</math>'s per <math>y\!</math> as there are, ''per'' things, things of the universe, then we have also the arithmetical equation:</p>
| the application of one relation to another.  So, a quaternion
+
|-
| being the relation of one vector to another, the multiplication
+
| align="center" | <math>[x][y] ~=~ [z].</math>
| of quaternions is the application of one such relation to a second.
+
|-
 
|
 
|
| Even ordinary numerical multiplication involves the same idea, for
+
<p>For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there are as many teeth to a Frenchman (perfect understood) as there are to any one of the universe, then:</p>
| 2 x 3 is a pair of triplets, and 3 x 2 is a triplet of pairs, where
+
|-
| "triplet of" and "pair of" are evidently relatives.
+
| align="center" | <math>[\mathit{t}][\mathrm{f}] ~=~ [\mathit{t}\mathrm{f}]</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| If we have an equation of the form:
+
<p>holds arithmetically.</p>
 +
 
 +
<p>So if men are just as apt to be black as things in general:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[\mathrm{m,}][\mathrm{b}] ~=~ [\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}]</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| xy  = z
+
<p>where the difference between <math>[\mathrm{m}]\!</math> and <math>[\mathrm{m,}]\!</math> must not be overlooked.</p>
 +
 
 +
<p>It is to be observed that:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[\mathit{1}] ~=~ \mathfrak{1}.</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| and there are just as many x's per y as there are,
+
<p>Boole was the first to show this connection between logic and probabilities.  He was restricted, however, to absolute terms. I do not remember having seen any extension of probability to relatives, except the ordinary theory of ''expectation''.</p>
| 'per' things, things of the universe, then we have
+
 
| also the arithmetical equation:
+
<p>Our logical multiplication, then, satisfies the essential conditions of multiplication, has a unity, has a conception similar to that of admitted multiplications, and contains numerical multiplication as a case under it.</p>
|
+
 
| [x][y]  =  [z].
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.76).</p>
|
+
|}
| For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there
 
| are as many teeth to a Frenchman (perfect understood)
 
| as there are to any one of the universe, then:
 
|
 
| ['t'][f]  =  ['t'f]
 
|
 
| holds arithmetically.
 
|
 
| So if men are just as apt to be black as things in general:
 
|
 
| [m,][b]  =  [m,b]
 
|
 
| where the difference between [m] and [m,] must not be overlooked.
 
|
 
| It is to be observed that:
 
|
 
| [!1!]  =  `1`.
 
|
 
| Boole was the first to show this connection between logic and
 
| probabilities.  He was restricted, however, to absolute terms.
 
| I do not remember having seen any extension of probability to
 
| relatives, except the ordinary theory of 'expectation'.
 
|
 
| Our logical multiplication, then, satisfies the essential conditions
 
| of multiplication, has a unity, has a conception similar to that of
 
| admitted multiplications, and contains numerical multiplication as
 
| a case under it.
 
|
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.76
 
|
 
| Charles Sanders Peirce,
 
|"Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives,
 
| Resulting from an Amplification of the Conceptions of Boole's Calculus of Logic",
 
|'Memoirs of the American Academy', Volume 9, pages 317-378, 26 January 1870,
 
|'Collected Papers' (CP 3.45-149), 'Chronological Edition' (CE 2, 359-429).
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.1===
 
===Commentary Note 11.1===
  
<pre>
+
We have reached a suitable place to pause in our reading of Peirce's text &mdash; actually, it's more like a place to run as fast as we can along a parallel track &mdash; where I can pay off a few of the expository IOUs I've been using to pave the way to this point.
We have reached in our reading of Peirce's text a suitable place to pause --
 
actually, it is more like to run as fast as we can along a parallel track --
 
where I can due quietus make of a few IOU's that I've used to pave my way.
 
  
The more pressing debts that come to mind are concerned with the matter
+
The more pressing debts that come to mind are concerned with the matter of Peirce's &ldquo;number of&rdquo; function that maps a term <math>t\!</math> into a number <math>[t],\!</math> and with my justification for calling a certain style of illustration the ''hypergraph picture'' of relational composition. As it happens, there is a thematic relation between these topics, and so I can make my way forward by addressing them together.
of Peirce's "number of" function, that maps a term t into a number [t],
 
and with my justification for calling a certain style of illustration
 
by the name of the "hypergraph" picture of relational composition.
 
As it happens, there is a thematic relation between these topics,
 
and so I can make my way forward by addressing them together.
 
  
At this point we have two good pictures of how to compute the
+
At this point we have two good pictures of how to compute the relational compositions of arbitrary dyadic relations, namely, the bigraph representation and the matrix representation, each of which has its differential advantages in different types of situations.
relational compositions of arbitrary 2-adic relations, namely,
 
the bigraph and the matrix representations, each of which has
 
its differential advantages in different types of situations.
 
  
But we do not have a comparable picture of how to compute the
+
But we do not have a comparable picture of how to compute the richer variety of relational compositions that involve triadic or any higher adicity relations.  As a matter of fact, we run into a non-trivial classification problem simply to enumerate the different types of compositions that arise in these cases.
richer variety of relational compositions that involve 3-adic
 
or any higher adicity relations.  As a matter of fact, we run
 
into a non-trivial classification problem simply to enumerate
 
the different types of compositions that arise in these cases.
 
  
Therefore, let us inaugurate a systematic study of relational composition,
+
Therefore, let us inaugurate a systematic study of relational composition, general enough to articulate the &ldquo;generative potency&rdquo; of Peirce's 1870 Logic of Relatives.
general enough to explicate the "generative potency" of Peirce's 1870 LOR.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.2===
 
===Commentary Note 11.2===
  
<pre>
+
Let's bring together the various things that Peirce has said about the &ldquo;number of function&rdquo; up to this point in the paper.
Let's bring together the various things that Peirce has said
 
about the "number of function" up to this point in the paper.
 
  
NOF 1.
+
====NOF 1====
  
| I propose to assign to all logical terms, numbers;
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
| to an absolute term, the number of individuals it denotes;
 
| to a relative term, the average number of things so related
 
| to one individual.
 
 
|
 
|
| Thus in a universe of perfect men ('men'),
+
<p>I propose to assign to all logical terms, numbers;  to an absolute term, the number of individuals it denotes;  to a relative term, the average number of things so related to one individual.  Thus in a universe of perfect men (''men''), the number of &ldquo;tooth of&rdquo; would be 32. The number of a relative with two correlates would be the average number of things so related to a pair of individuals; and so on for relatives of higher numbers of correlates. I propose to denote the number of a logical term by enclosing the term in square brackets, thus <math>[t].\!</math></p>
| the number of "tooth of" would be 32.
+
 
|
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.65).</p>
| The number of a relative with two correlates would be the
+
|}
| average number of things so related to a pair of individuals;
 
| and so on for relatives of higher numbers of correlates.
 
|
 
| I propose to denote the number of a logical term by
 
| enclosing the term in square brackets, thus ['t'].
 
|
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.65
 
  
NOF 2.
+
====NOF 2====
  
| But not only do the significations of '=' and '<' here adopted fulfill all
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
| absolute requirements, but they have the supererogatory virtue of being very
 
| nearly the same as the common significations.  Equality is, in fact, nothing
 
| but the identity of two numbers;  numbers that are equal are those which are
 
| predicable of the same collections, just as terms that are identical are those
 
| which are predicable of the same classes.  So, to write 5 < 7 is to say that 5
 
| is part of 7, just as to write f < m is to say that Frenchmen are part of men.
 
| Indeed, if f < m, then the number of Frenchmen is less than the number of men,
 
| and if v = p, then the number of Vice-Presidents is equal to the number of
 
| Presidents of the Senate;  so that the numbers may always be substituted
 
| for the terms themselves, in case no signs of operation occur in the
 
| equations or inequalities.
 
 
|
 
|
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.66
+
<p>But not only do the significations of <math>~=~</math> and <math>~<~</math> here adopted fulfill all absolute requirements, but they have the supererogatory virtue of being very nearly the same as the common significations. Equality is, in fact, nothing but the identity of two numbers;  numbers that are equal are those which are predicable of the same collections, just as terms that are identical are those which are predicable of the same classes. So, to write <math>~5 < 7~</math> is to say that <math>~5~</math> is part of <math>~7~</math>, just as to write <math>~\mathrm{f} < \mathrm{m}~</math> is to say that Frenchmen are part of men.  Indeed, if <math>~\mathrm{f} < \mathrm{m}~</math>, then the number of Frenchmen is less than the number of men, and if <math>~\mathrm{v} = \mathrm{p}~</math>, then the number of Vice-Presidents is equal to the number of Presidents of the Senate;  so that the numbers may always be substituted for the terms themselves, in case no signs of operation occur in the equations or inequalities.</p>
  
NOF 3.
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.66).</p>
 +
|}
  
| It is plain that both the regular non-invertible addition
+
====NOF 3====
| and the invertible addition satisfy the absolute conditions.
+
 
| But the notation has other recommendations.  The conception
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
| of 'taking together' involved in these processes is strongly
 
| analogous to that of summation, the sum of 2 and 5, for example,
 
| being the number of a collection which consists of a collection of
 
| two and a collection of five.  Any logical equation or inequality
 
| in which no operation but addition is involved may be converted
 
| into a numerical equation or inequality by substituting the
 
| numbers of the several terms for the terms themselves --
 
| provided all the terms summed are mutually exclusive.
 
 
|
 
|
| Addition being taken in this sense,
+
<p>It is plain that both the regular non-invertible addition and the invertible addition satisfy the absolute conditions.  But the notation has other recommendations.  The conception of ''taking together'' involved in these processes is strongly analogous to that of summation, the sum of 2 and 5, for example, being the number of a collection which consists of a collection of two and a collection of five.  Any logical equation or inequality in which no operation but addition is involved may be converted into a numerical equation or inequality by substituting the numbers of the several terms for the terms themselves &mdash; provided all the terms summed are mutually exclusive.</p>
| 'nothing' is to be denoted by 'zero',
+
 
| for then:
+
<p>Addition being taken in this sense, ''nothing'' is to be denoted by ''zero'', for then</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>x ~+\!\!,~ 0 ~=~ x</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| x +, 0 = x
+
<p>whatever is denoted by <math>~x~</math>;  and this is the definition of ''zero''.  This interpretation is given by Boole, and is very neat, on account of the resemblance between the ordinary conception of ''zero'' and that of nothing, and because we shall thus have</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[0] ~=~ 0.</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| whatever is denoted by x;  and this is the definition
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.67).</p>
| of 'zero'.  This interpretation is given by Boole, and
+
|}
| is very neat, on account of the resemblance between the
+
 
| ordinary conception of 'zero' and that of nothing, and
+
====NOF 4====
| because we shall thus have
+
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 
|
 
|
| [0] =  0.
+
<p>The conception of multiplication we have adopted is that of the application of one relation to another. &hellip;</p>
|
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.67
 
  
NOF 4.
+
<p>Even ordinary numerical multiplication involves the same idea, for <math>~2 \times 3~</math> is a pair of triplets, and <math>~3 \times 2~</math> is a triplet of pairs, where &ldquo;triplet of&rdquo; and &ldquo;pair of&rdquo; are evidently relatives.</p>
  
| The conception of multiplication we have adopted is
+
<p>If we have an equation of the form:</p>
| that of the application of one relation to another.  ...
+
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>xy ~=~ z</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| Even ordinary numerical multiplication involves the same idea,
+
<p>and there are just as many <math>x\!</math>'s per <math>y\!</math> as there are, ''per'' things, things of the universe, then we have also the arithmetical equation:</p>
| for 2 x 3 is a pair of triplets, and 3 x 2 is a triplet of pairs,
+
|-
| where "triplet of" and "pair of" are evidently relatives.
+
| align="center" | <math>[x][y] ~=~ [z].</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| If we have an equation of the form:
+
<p>For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there are as many teeth to a Frenchman (perfect understood) as there are to any one of the universe, then:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[\mathit{t}][\mathrm{f}] ~=~ [\mathit{t}\mathrm{f}]</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| xy  = z
+
<p>holds arithmetically.</p>
 +
 
 +
<p>So if men are just as apt to be black as things in general:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[\mathrm{m,}][\mathrm{b}] ~=~ [\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}]</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| and there are just as many x's per y as there are,
+
<p>where the difference between <math>[\mathrm{m}]\!</math> and <math>[\mathrm{m,}]\!</math> must not be overlooked.</p>
| 'per' things, things of the universe, then we have
+
 
| also the arithmetical equation:
+
<p>It is to be observed that:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[\mathit{1}] ~=~ \mathfrak{1}.</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| [x][y]  =  [z].
+
<p>Boole was the first to show this connection between logic and probabilities.  He was restricted, however, to absolute terms. I do not remember having seen any extension of probability to relatives, except the ordinary theory of ''expectation''.</p>
|
 
| For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there
 
| are as many teeth to a Frenchman (perfect understood)
 
| as there are to any one of the universe, then:
 
|
 
| ['t'][f]  =  ['t'f]
 
|
 
| holds arithmetically.
 
|
 
| So if men are just as apt to be black as things in general:
 
|
 
| [m,][b]  =  [m,b]
 
|
 
| where the difference between [m] and [m,] must not be overlooked.
 
|
 
| It is to be observed that:
 
|
 
| [!1!]  =  `1`.
 
|
 
| Boole was the first to show this connection between logic and
 
| probabilities.  He was restricted, however, to absolute terms.
 
| I do not remember having seen any extension of probability to
 
| relatives, except the ordinary theory of 'expectation'.
 
|
 
| Our logical multiplication, then, satisfies the essential conditions
 
| of multiplication, has a unity, has a conception similar to that of
 
| admitted multiplications, and contains numerical multiplication as
 
| a case under it.
 
|
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.76
 
 
 
Before I can discuss Peirce's "number of" function in greater detail
 
I will need to deal with an expositional difficulty that I have been
 
very carefully dancing around all this time, but that will no longer
 
abide its assigned place under the rug.
 
  
Functions have long been understood, from well before Peirce's time to ours,
+
<p>Our logical multiplication, then, satisfies the essential conditions of multiplication, has a unity, has a conception similar to that of admitted multiplications, and contains numerical multiplication as a case under it.</p>
as special cases of 2-adic relations, so the "number of" function itself is
 
already to be numbered among the types of 2-adic relatives that we've been
 
explictly mentioning and implicitly using all this time.  But Peirce's way
 
of talking about a 2-adic relative term is to list the "relate" first and
 
the "correlate" second, a convention that goes over into functional terms
 
as making the functional value first and the functional antecedent second,
 
whereas almost anyone brought up in our present time frame has difficulty
 
thinking of a function any other way than as a set of ordered pairs where
 
the order in each pair lists the functional argument, or domain element,
 
first and the functional value, or codomain element, second.
 
  
It is possible to work all this out in a very nice way within a very general context
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.76).</p>
of flexible conventions, but not without introducing an order of anachronisms into
+
|}
Peirce's presentation that I am presently trying to avoid as much as possible.
 
Thus, I will need to experiment with various sorts of compromise formations.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.3===
 
===Commentary Note 11.3===
  
<pre>
+
Before I can discuss Peirce's &ldquo;number of&rdquo; function in greater detail I will need to deal with an expositional difficulty that I have been very carefully dancing around all this time, but one that will no longer abide its assigned place under the rug.
Having spent a fair amount of time in earnest reflection on the issue,
 
I cannot see a way to continue my interpretation of Peirce's 1870 LOR,
 
to master the distance between his conventions of presentation and my
 
present personal perspectives on relations, without introducing a few
 
interpretive anachronisms and other artifacts in the process, and the
 
only excuse that I can make for myself is that at least these will be
 
novel sorts of anachronisms and artifacts in comparison with the ones
 
that the reeder may alreedy have seen.  A poor excuse, but all I have.
 
The least that I can do, then, and I'm something of an expert on that,
 
is to exposit my personal interpretive apparatus on a separate thread,
 
where it will not distract too much from the intellectual canon, that
 
is to opine, the "thinking panpipe" that we find in Peirce's 1870 LOR.
 
  
Ripped from the pages of my dissertation, then, I will lay out
+
Functions have long been understood, from well before Peirce's time to ours, as special cases of dyadic relations, so the &ldquo;number of&rdquo; function itself is already to be numbered among the types of dyadic relatives that we've been explicitly mentioning and implicitly using all this time.  But Peirce's way of talking about a dyadic relative term is to list the &ldquo;relate&rdquo; first and the &ldquo;correlate&rdquo; second, a convention that goes over into functional terms as making the functional value first and the functional argument second, whereas almost anyone brought up in our present time frame has difficulty thinking of a function any other way than as a set of ordered pairs where the order in each pair lists the functional argument first and the functional value second.
some samples of background material on "Relations In General",
 
as spied from a combinatorial point of view, that I hope will
 
serve in reeding Peirce's text, if we draw on it judiciously.
 
</pre>
 
  
===Commentary Note 11.4===
+
All of these syntactic wrinkles can be ironed out in a very smooth way, given a sufficiently general context of flexible enough interpretive conventions, but not without introducing an order of anachronism into Peirce's presentation that I am presently trying to avoid as much as possible.  Thus, I will need to experiment with various styles of compromise formation.
  
<pre>
+
The interpretation of Peirce's 1870 &ldquo;Logic of Relatives&rdquo; can be facilitated by introducing a few items of background material on relations in general, as regarded from a combinatorial point of view.
The task before us now is to get very clear about the relationships
 
among relative terms, relations, and the special cases of relations
 
that are constituted by equivalence relations, functions, and so on.
 
  
I am optimistic that the some of the tethering material that I spun
+
===Commentary Note 11.4===
along the "Relations In General" (RIG) thread will help us to track
 
the equivalential and functional properties of special relations in
 
a way that will not weigh too heavy on the rather capricious lineal
 
embedding of syntax in 1-dimensional strings on 2-dimensional pages.
 
But I cannot see far enough ahead to forsee all the consequences of
 
trying this tack, and so I cannot help but to be a bit experimental.
 
  
The first obstacle to get past is the order convention
+
The task before us is to clarify the relationships among relative terms, relations, and the special cases of relations that are given by equivalence relations, functions, and so on.
that Peirce's orientation to relative terms causes him
 
to use for functions.  By way of making our discussion
 
concrete, and directing our attentions to an immediate
 
object example, let us say that we desire to represent
 
the "number of" function, that Peirce denotes by means
 
of square brackets, by means of a 2-adic relative term,
 
say 'v', where 'v'(t) = [t] = the number of the term t.
 
  
To set the 2-adic relative term 'v' within a suitable context of interpretation,
+
The first obstacle to get past is the order convention that Peirce's orientation to relative terms causes him to use for functionsTo focus on a concrete example of immediate use in this discussion, let's take the &ldquo;number of&rdquo; function that Peirce denotes by means of square brackets and re-formulate it as a dyadic relative term <math>v\!</math> as follows:
let us suppose that 'v' corresponds to a relation V c R x S, where R is the set
 
of real numbers and S is a suitable syntactic domain, here described as "terms".
 
Then the 2-adic relation V is evidently a function from S to RWe might think
 
to use the plain letter "v" to denote this function, as v : S -> R, but I worry
 
this may be a chaos waiting to happen.  Also, I think that we should anticipate
 
the very great likelihood that we cannot always assign numbers to every term in
 
whatever syntactic domain S that we choose, so it is probably better to account
 
the 2-adic relation V as a partial function from S to R.  All things considered,
 
then, let me try out the following impedimentaria of strategies and compromises.
 
  
First, I will adapt the functional arrow notation so that it allows us
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
to detach the functional orientation from the order in which the names
+
| <math>v(t) ~:=~ [t] ~=~ \text{the number of the term}~ t.\!</math>
of domains are written on the page. Second, I will need to change the
+
|}
notation for "pre-functions", or "partial functions", from one likely
 
confound to a slightly less likely confound.  This gives the scheme:
 
  
  q : X -> Y means that q is functional at X.
+
To set the dyadic relative term <math>v\!</math> within a suitable context of interpretation, let us suppose that <math>v\!</math> corresponds to a relation <math>V \subseteq \mathbb{R} \times S,\!</math> where <math>\mathbb{R}\!</math> is the set of real numbers and <math>S\!</math> is a suitable syntactic domain, here described as a set of ''terms''.  The dyadic relation <math>V\!</math> is at first sight a function from <math>S\!</math> to <math>\mathbb{R}.\!</math>  There is, however, a very great likelihood that we cannot always assign numbers to every term in whatever syntactic domain <math>S\!</math> we happen to choose, so we may eventually be forced to treat the dyadic relation <math>V\!</math> as a partial function from <math>S\!</math> to <math>\mathbb{R}.\!</math>  All things considered, then, let me try out the following impedimentaria of strategies and compromises.
  
  q : X <- Y means that q is functional at Y.
+
First, I adapt the functional arrow notation so that it allows us to detach the functional orientation from the order in which the names of domains are written on the page.  Second, I change the notation for ''partial functions'', or ''pre-functions'', to one that is less likely to be confounded. This gives the scheme:
  
  q : X ~> Y means that q is pre-functional at X.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>q : X \to Y\!</math> means that <math>q\!</math> is functional at <math>X.\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| <math>q : X \leftarrow Y\!</math> means that <math>q\!</math> is functional at <math>Y.\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| <math>q : X \rightharpoonup Y\!</math> means that <math>q\!</math> is pre-functional at <math>X.\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| <math>q : X \leftharpoonup Y\!</math> means that <math>q\!</math> is pre-functional at <math>Y.\!</math>
 +
|}
  
  q : X <~ Y means that q is pre-functional at Y.
+
Until it becomes necessary to stipulate otherwise, let us assume that <math>v\!</math> is a function in <math>\mathbb{R}\!</math> of <math>S,\!</math> written <math>v : \mathbb{R} \leftarrow S,\!</math> amounting to the functional alias of the dyadic relation <math>V \subseteq \mathbb{R} \times S\!</math> and associated with the dyadic relative term <math>v\!</math> whose relate lies in the set <math>\mathbb{R}\!</math> of real numbers and whose correlate lies in the set <math>S\!</math> of syntactic terms.
  
For now, I will pretend that v is a function in R of S, v : R <- S,
+
'''Note.'''  See the article [[Relation Theory]] for the definitions of ''functions'' and ''pre-functions'' used in this section.
amounting to the functional alias of the 2-adic relation V c R x S,
 
and associated with the 2-adic relative term 'v' whose relate lies
 
in the set R of real numbers and whose correlate lies in the set S
 
of syntactic terms.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.5===
 
===Commentary Note 11.5===
  
<pre>
+
The right form of diagram can be a great aid in rendering complex matters comprehensible, so let's extract the overly compressed bits of the &ldquo;[[Relation Theory]]&rdquo; article that we need to illuminate Peirce's 1870 &ldquo;Logic Of Relatives&rdquo; and draw what icons we can within the current frame.
It always helps me to draw lots of pictures of stuff,
 
so let's extract the somewhat overly compressed bits
 
of the "Relations In General" thread that we'll need
 
right away for the applications to Peirce's 1870 LOR,
 
and draw what icons we can within the frame of Ascii.
 
  
For the immediate present, we may start with 2-adic relations
+
For the immediate present, we may start with dyadic relations and describe the customary species of relations and functions in terms of their local and numerical incidence properties.
and describe the customary species of relations and functions
 
in terms of their local and numerical incidence properties.
 
  
Let P c X x Y be an arbitrary 2-adic relation.
+
Let <math>P \subseteq X \times Y\!</math> be an arbitrary dyadic relation. The following properties of <math>P\!</math> can be defined:
The following properties of P can be defined:
 
  
P is "total" at X     iff   P is (>=1)-regular at X.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
P ~\text{is total at}~ X
 +
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is}~ (\ge 1)\text{-regular}~ \text{at}~ X.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
P ~\text{is total at}~ Y
 +
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is}~ (\ge 1)\text{-regular}~ \text{at}~ Y.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
P ~\text{is tubular at}~ X
 +
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is}~ (\le 1)\text{-regular}~ \text{at}~ X.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
P ~\text{is tubular at}~ Y
 +
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is}~ (\le 1)\text{-regular}~ \text{at}~ Y.
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
P is "total" at Y     iff  P is (>=1)-regular at Y.
+
If <math>P \subseteq X \times Y\!</math> is tubular at <math>X,\!</math> then <math>P\!</math> is known as a ''partial function'' or a ''pre-function'' from <math>X\!</math> to <math>Y,\!</math> frequently signalized by renaming <math>P\!</math> with an alternate lower case name, say <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} p {}^{\prime\prime},~\!</math> and writing <math>p : X \rightharpoonup Y.\!</math>
  
P is "tubular" at X  iff  P is (=<1)-regular at X.
+
Just by way of formalizing the definition:
  
P is "tubular" at Y   iff   P is (=<1)-regular at Y.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
P ~\text{is a pre-function}~ P : X \rightharpoonup Y
 +
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is tubular at}~ X.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
P ~\text{is a pre-function}~ P : X \leftharpoonup Y
 +
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is tubular at}~ Y.
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
To illustrate these properties, let us fashion
+
To illustrate these properties, let us fashion a generic enough example of a dyadic relation, <math>E \subseteq X \times Y,~\!</math> where <math>X = Y = \{ 0, 1, \ldots, 8, 9 \},\!</math> and where the bigraph picture of <math>E\!</math> looks like this:
a "generic enough" example of a 2-adic relation,
 
E c X x Y, where X = Y = {0, 1, ..., 8, 9}, and
 
where the bigraph picture of E looks like this:
 
  
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  X
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 30.jpg]] || (30)
    \  |\ /|\  \  \  |   |\
+
|}
      \ | / | \  \  \ |   | \        E
 
      \|/ \|  \  \  \|  |  \
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  Y
 
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
  
If we scan along the X dimension we see that the "Y incidence degrees"
+
If we scan along the <math>X\!</math> dimension from <math>0\!</math> to <math>9\!</math> we see that the incidence degrees of the <math>X\!</math> nodes with the <math>Y\!</math> domain are <math>0, 1, 2, 3, 1, 1, 1, 2, 0, 0,\!</math> in that order.
of the X nodes 0 through 9 are 0, 1, 2, 3, 1, 1, 1, 2, 0, 0, in order.
 
  
If we scan along the Y dimension we see that the "X incidence degrees"
+
If we scan along the <math>Y\!</math> dimension from <math>0\!</math> to <math>9\!</math> we see that the incidence degrees of the <math>Y\!</math> nodes with the <math>X\!</math> domain are <math>0, 0, 3, 2, 1, 1, 2, 1, 1, 0,\!</math> in that order.
of the Y nodes 0 through 9 are 0, 0, 3, 2, 1, 1, 2, 1, 1, 0, in order.
 
  
Thus, E is not total at either X or Y,
+
Thus, <math>E\!</math> is not total at either <math>X\!</math> or <math>Y,\!</math> since there are nodes in both <math>X\!</math> and <math>Y\!</math> having incidence degrees less than <math>1.\!</math>
since there are nodes in both X and Y
 
having incidence degrees that equal 0.
 
  
Also, E is not tubular at either X or Y,
+
Also, <math>E\!</math> is not tubular at either <math>X\!</math> or <math>Y,\!</math> since there are nodes in both <math>X\!</math> and <math>Y\!</math> having incidence degrees greater than <math>1.\!</math>
since there exist nodes in both X and Y
 
having incidence degrees greater than 1.
 
  
Clearly, then, E cannot qualify as a pre-function
+
Clearly, then, the relation <math>E\!</math> cannot qualify as a pre-function, much less as a function on either of its relational domains.
or a function on either of its relational domains.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.6===
 
===Commentary Note 11.6===
  
<pre>
+
Let's continue working our way through the above definitions, constructing appropriate examples as we go.
Let's continue to work our way through the rest of the first
 
set of definitions, making up appropriate examples as we go.
 
 
 
| Let P c X x Y be an arbitrary 2-adic relation.
 
| The following properties of P can be defined:
 
|
 
| P is "total" at X    iff  P is (>=1)-regular at X.
 
|
 
| P is "total" at Y    iff  P is (>=1)-regular at Y.
 
|
 
| P is "tubular" at X  iff  P is (=<1)-regular at X.
 
|
 
| P is "tubular" at Y  iff  P is (=<1)-regular at Y.
 
  
E_1 exemplifies the quality of "totality at X".
+
<math>E_1\!</math> exemplifies the quality of ''totality at <math>X.\!</math>''
  
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  X
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 31.jpg]] || (31)
\  \  |\ /|\  \  \  |  |\  \  |
+
|}
  \  \ | / | \  \  \ |   | \  \ |   E_1
 
  \  \|/ \|  \  \  \|   |  \  \|
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  Y
 
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
  
E_2 exemplifies the quality of "totality at Y".
+
<math>E_2\!</math> exemplifies the quality of ''totality at <math>Y.\!</math>''
  
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  X
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 32.jpg]] || (32)
|\  \  |\ /|\  \  \  |  |\  \
+
|}
| \  \ | / | \  \  \ |   | \  \    E_2
 
| \  \|/ \|  \  \  \|  |  \  \
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  Y
 
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
  
E_3 exemplifies the quality of "tubularity at X".
+
<math>E_3\!</math> exemplifies the quality of ''tubularity at <math>X.\!</math>''
  
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  X
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 33.jpg]] || (33)
    \  |  /    \  \  |  |
+
|}
      \ | /      \  \ |   |           E_3
 
      \|/        \  \|  |
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  Y
 
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
  
E_4 exemplifies the quality of "tubularity at Y".
+
<math>E_4\!</math> exemplifies the quality of ''tubularity at <math>Y.\!</math>''
  
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  X
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 34.jpg]] || (34)
          /|\  \  \      |\
+
|}
          / | \  \  \    | \        E_4
 
        /  | \  \  \    |  \
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  Y
 
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
  
| If P c X x Y is tubular at X, then P is known as a "partial function"
+
So <math>E_3\!</math> is a pre-function <math>e_3 : X \rightharpoonup Y,\!</math> and <math>E_4\!</math> is a pre-function <math>e_4 : X \leftharpoonup Y.\!</math>
| or a "pre-function" from X to Y, frequently signalized by renaming P
 
| with an alternative lower case name, say "p", and writing p : X ~> Y.
 
|
 
| Just by way of formalizing the definition:
 
|
 
| P is a "pre-function" P : X ~> Y  iff  P is tubular at X.
 
|
 
| P is a "pre-function" P : X <~ Y  iff  P is tubular at Y.
 
 
 
So, E_3 is a pre-function e_3 : X ~> Y,
 
and E_4 is a pre-function e_4 : X <~ Y.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.7===
 
===Commentary Note 11.7===
  
<pre>
+
We come now to the very special cases of dyadic relations that are known as ''functions''.  It will serve a dual purpose on behalf of the present exposition if we take the class of functions as a source of object examples to clarify the more abstruse concepts in the [[Relation Theory]] material.
We come now to the very special cases of 2-adic relations that are
 
known as functions.  It will serve a dual purpose on behalf of the
 
exposition if we take the class of functions as a source of object
 
examples to clarify the more abstruse concepts in the RIG material.
 
  
To begin, let's recall the definition of a local flag:
+
To begin, let's recall the definition of a ''local flag'':
  
L_x@j = {<x_1, ..., x_j, ..., x_k> in L : x_j = x}.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>L_{x \,\text{at}\, j} = \{ (x_1, \ldots, x_j, \ldots, x_k) \in L : x_j = x \}.\!</math>
 +
|}
  
In the case of a 2-adic relation L c X_1 x X_2 = X x Y,
+
In the case of a dyadic relation <math>L \subseteq X_1 \times X_2 = X \times Y,\!</math> it is possible to simplify the notation for local flags in a couple of waysFirst, it is often easier in the dyadic case to refer to <math>L_{u \,\text{at}\, 1}\!</math> as <math>L_{u \,\text{at}\, X}\!</math> and <math>L_{v \,\text{at}\, 2}\!</math> as <math>L_{v \,\text{at}\, Y}.\!</math>  Second, the notation may be streamlined even further by writing <math>L_{u \,\text{at}\, 1}\!</math> as <math>u \star L\!</math> and <math>L_{v \,\text{at}\, 2}\!</math> as <math>L \star v.\!</math>
we can reap the benefits of a radical simplification in
 
the definitions of the local flagsAlso in this case,
 
we tend to denote L_u@1 by "L_u@X" and L_v@2 by "L_v@Y".
 
  
In the light of these considerations, the local flags of
+
In light of these considerations, the local flags of a dyadic relation <math>L \subseteq X \times Y\!</math> may be formulated as follows:
a 2-adic relation L c X x Y may be formulated as follows:
 
  
L_u@X = {<x, y> in L : x = u}
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
u \star L
 +
& = &
 +
L_{u \,\text{at}\, X}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\{ (u, y) \in L \}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\text{the ordered pairs in}~ L ~\text{that are incident with}~ u \in X.
 +
\\[9pt]
 +
L \star v
 +
& = &
 +
L_{v \,\text{at}\, Y}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\{ (x, v) \in L \}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\text{the ordered pairs in}~ L ~\text{that are incident with}~ v \in Y.
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
      =  the set of all ordered pairs in L incident with u in X.
+
The following definitions are also useful:
  
L_v@Y = {<x, y> in L : y = v}
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
u \cdot L
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{proj}_2 (u \star L)
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\{ y \in Y : (u, y) \in L \}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\text{the elements of}~ Y ~\text{that are}~ L\text{-related to}~ u.
 +
\\[9pt]
 +
L \cdot v
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{proj}_1 (L \star v)
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\{ x \in X : (x, v) \in L \}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\text{the elements of}~ X ~\text{that are}~ L\text{-related to}~ v.
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
      =  the set of all ordered pairs in L incident with v in Y.
+
A sufficient illustration is supplied by the earlier example <math>E.\!</math>
  
A sufficient illustration is supplied by the earlier example E.
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 30.jpg]] || (35)
 +
|}
  
0  1  2  3   4  5  6  7  8  9
+
The local flag <math>E_{3 \,\text{at}\, X}\!</math> is displayed here:
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  X
 
    \ |\ /|\   \  \  |  |\
 
      \ | / | \  \  \ |  | \        E
 
      \|/ \|  \  \  \|  |  \
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  Y
 
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
  
The local flag E_3@X is displayed here:
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 36 ISW.jpg]] || (36)
 +
|}
  
0  1  2   3  4  5  6  7  8  9
+
The local flag <math>E_{2 \,\text{at}\, Y}\!</math> is displayed here:
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  X
 
          /|\
 
          / | \                         E_3@X
 
        /  |  \
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  Y
 
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
  
The local flag E_2@Y is displayed here:
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 37 ISW.jpg]] || (37)
 +
|}
  
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8   9
+
===Commentary Note 11.8===
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  X
 
    \  |  /
 
      \ | /                            E_2@Y
 
      \|/
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  Y
 
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
</pre>
 
  
===Commentary Note 11.8===
+
Next let's re-examine the ''numerical incidence properties'' of relations, concentrating on the definitions of the assorted regularity conditions.
 +
 
 +
For example, <math>L\!</math> is said to be <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} c\text{-regular at}~ j \, {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> if and only if the cardinality of the local flag <math>L_{x \,\text{at}\, j}\!</math> is equal to <math>c\!</math> for all <math>x \in X_j,\!</math> coded in symbols, if and only if <math>|L_{x \,\text{at}\, j}| = c\!</math> for all <math>{x \in X_j}.\!</math>
  
<pre>
+
In a similar fashion, it is possible to define the numerical incidence properties <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime}(< c)\text{-regular at}~ j \, {}^{\prime\prime},\!</math> <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime}(> c)\text{-regular at}~ j \, {}^{\prime\prime},\!</math> and so on.  For ease of reference, a few of these definitions are recorded below.
Now let's re-examine the "numerical incidence properties" of relations,
 
concentrating on the definitions of the assorted regularity conditions.
 
  
| For instance, L is said to be "c-regular at j" if and only if
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
| the cardinality of the local flag L_x@j is c for all x in X_j,
 
| coded in symbols, if and only if |L_x@j| = c for all x in X_j.
 
|
 
| In a similar fashion, one can define the NIP's "<c-regular at j",
 
| ">c-regular at j", and so on.  For ease of reference, I record a
 
| few of these definitions here:
 
|
 
| L is  c-regular at j      iff  |L_x@j|  = c for all x in X_j.
 
|
 
| L is (<c)-regular at j    iff  |L_x@j|  < c for all x in X_j.
 
|
 
| L is (>c)-regular at j    iff  |L_x@j|  > c for all x in X_j.
 
|
 
| L is (=<c)-regular at j  iff  |L_x@j|  =< c for all x in X_j.
 
 
|
 
|
| L is (>=c)-regular at j   iff   |L_x@j| >= c for all x in X_j.
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
L ~\text{is}~ c\text{-regular at}~ j
 +
& \iff &
 +
|L_{x \,\text{at}\, j}| = c ~\text{for all}~ x \in X_j.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
L ~\text{is}~ (< c)\text{-regular at}~ j
 +
& \iff &
 +
|L_{x \,\text{at}\, j}| < c ~\text{for all}~ x \in X_j.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
L ~\text{is}~ (> c)\text{-regular at}~ j
 +
& \iff &
 +
|L_{x \,\text{at}\, j}| > c ~\text{for all}~ x \in X_j.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
L ~\text{is}~ (\le c)\text{-regular at}~ j
 +
& \iff &
 +
|L_{x \,\text{at}\, j}| \le c ~\text{for all}~ x \in X_j.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
L ~\text{is}~ (\ge c)\text{-regular at}~ j
 +
& \iff &
 +
|L_{x \,\text{at}\, j}| \ge c ~\text{for all}~ x \in X_j.
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
Clearly, if any relation is (=<c)-regular on one
+
Clearly, if any relation is <math>(\le c)\text{-regular}\!</math> on one of its domains <math>X_j~\!</math> and also <math>(\ge c)\text{-regular}\!</math> on the same domain, then it must be <math>(= c)\text{-regular}\!</math> on that domain, in effect, <math>c\text{-regular}\!</math> at <math>j.\!</math>
of its domains X_j and also (>=c)-regular on the
 
same domain, then it must be (=c)-regular on the
 
affected domain X_j, in effect, c-regular at j.
 
  
For example, let G = {r, s, t} and H = {1, ..., 9},
+
For example, let <math>G = \{ r, s, t \}\!</math> and <math>H = \{ 1, \ldots, 9 \},\!</math> and consider the dyadic relation <math>F \subseteq G \times H\!</math> that is bigraphed here:
and consider the 2-adic relation F c G x H that is
 
bigraphed here:
 
  
    r          s          t
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
    o          o          o      G
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 38.jpg]] || (38)
  /|\        /|\        /|\
+
|}
  / | \      / | \      / | \    F
 
/  |  \    /  |  \    /  | \
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  H
 
1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
  
We observe that F is 3-regular at G and 1-regular at H.
+
We observe that <math>F\!</math> is 3-regular at <math>G\!</math> and 1-regular at <math>H.\!</math>
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.9===
 
===Commentary Note 11.9===
  
<pre>
+
Among the variety of conceivable regularities affecting dyadic relations we pay special attention to the <math>c\!</math>-regularity conditions where <math>c\!</math> is equal to 1.
Among the vast variety of conceivable regularities affecting 2-adic relations,
 
we pay special attention to the c-regularity conditions where c is equal to 1.
 
  
| Let P c X x Y be an arbitrary 2-adic relation.
+
Let <math>P \subseteq X \times Y\!</math> be an arbitrary dyadic relation. The following properties of <math>P\!</math> can be defined:
| The following properties of P can be defined:
+
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| P is "total" at X     iff   P is (>=1)-regular at X.
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
|
+
P ~\text{is total at}~ X
| P is "total" at Y     iff   P is (>=1)-regular at Y.
+
& \iff &
|
+
P ~\text{is}~ (\ge 1)\text{-regular}~ \text{at}~ X.
| P is "tubular" at X   iff   P is (=<1)-regular at X.
+
\\[6pt]
 +
P ~\text{is total at}~ Y
 +
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is}~ (\ge 1)\text{-regular}~ \text{at}~ Y.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
P ~\text{is tubular at}~ X
 +
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is}~ (\le 1)\text{-regular}~ \text{at}~ X.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
P ~\text{is tubular at}~ Y
 +
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is}~ (\le 1)\text{-regular}~ \text{at}~ Y.
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
We have already looked at dyadic relations that separately exemplify each of these regularities.  We also introduced a few bits of additional terminology and special-purpose notations for working with tubular relations:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| P is "tubular" at Y   iff   P is (=<1)-regular at Y.
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
P ~\text{is a pre-function}~ P : X \rightharpoonup Y
 +
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is tubular at}~ X.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
P ~\text{is a pre-function}~ P : X \leftharpoonup Y
 +
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is tubular at}~ Y.
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
We have already looked at 2-adic relations that
+
We arrive by way of this winding stair at the special stamps of dyadic relations <math>P \subseteq X \times Y\!</math> that are variously described as ''1-regular'', ''total and tubular'', or ''total prefunctions'' on specified domains, either <math>X\!</math> or <math>Y\!</math> or both, and that are more often celebrated as ''functions'' on those domains.
separately exemplify each of these regularities.
 
  
Also, we introduced a few bits of additional terminology and
+
If <math>P\!</math> is a pre-function <math>P : X \rightharpoonup Y\!</math> that happens to be total at <math>X,\!</math> then <math>P\!</math> is known as a ''function'' from <math>X\!</math> to <math>Y,\!</math> typically indicated as <math>{P : X \to Y}.\!</math>
special-purpose notations for working with tubular relations:
 
 
 
| P is a "pre-function" P : X ~> Y  iff  P is tubular at X.
 
|
 
| P is a "pre-function" P : X <~ Y   iff  P is tubular at Y.
 
  
Thus, we arrive by way of this winding stair at the very special stamps
+
To say that a relation <math>P \subseteq X \times Y\!</math> is ''totally tubular'' at <math>X\!</math> is to say that <math>P\!</math> is 1-regular at <math>X.\!</math>  Thus, we may formalize the following definitions:
of 2-adic relations P c X x Y that are "total prefunctions" at X (or Y),
 
"total and tubular" at X (or Y), or "1-regular" at X (or Y), more often
 
celebrated as "functions" at X (or Y).
 
  
| If P is a pre-function P : X ~> Y that happens to be total at X, then P
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
| is known as a "function" from X to Y, typically indicated as P : X -> Y.
 
|
 
| To say that a relation P c X x Y is totally tubular at X is to say that
 
| it is 1-regular at X.  Thus, we may formalize the following definitions:
 
 
|
 
|
| P is a "function" p : X -> Y   iff   P is 1-regular at X.
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
|
+
P ~\text{is a function}~ P : X \to Y
| P is a "function" p : X <- Y   iff   P is 1-regular at Y.
+
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is}~ 1\text{-regular at}~ X.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
P ~\text{is a function}~ P : X \leftarrow Y
 +
& \iff &
 +
P ~\text{is}~ 1\text{-regular at}~ Y.
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
For example, let X = Y = {0, ..., 9} and let F c X x Y be
+
For example, let <math>X = Y = \{ 0, \ldots, 9 \}\!</math> and let <math>F \subseteq X \times Y\!</math> be the dyadic relation depicted in the bigraph below:
the 2-adic relation that is depicted in the bigraph below:
 
  
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  X
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 39.jpg]] || (39)
\ /      /|\  \      |  |\  \
+
|}
  \      / | \  \    |   | \  \    F
 
/ \    /  |  \  \    |  | \  \
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  Y
 
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
  
We observe that F is a function at Y,
+
We observe that <math>F\!</math> is a function at <math>Y\!</math> and we record this fact in either of the manners <math>F : X \leftarrow Y\!</math> or <math>F : Y \to X.\!</math>
and we record this fact in either of
 
the manners F : X <- Y or F : Y -> X.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.10===
 
===Commentary Note 11.10===
  
<pre>
+
In the case of a dyadic relation <math>F \subseteq X \times Y\!</math> that has the qualifications of a function <math>f : X \to Y,\!</math> there are a number of further differentia that arise:
In the case of a 2-adic relation F c X x Y that has
 
the qualifications of a function f : X -> Y, there
 
are a number of further differentia that arise:
 
  
| f is "surjective"   iff  f is total at Y.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| f is "injective"    iff   f is tubular at Y.
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
|
+
f ~\text{is surjective} & \iff & f ~\text{is total at}~ Y.
| f is "bijective"    iff   f is 1-regular at Y.
+
\\[6pt]
 +
f ~\text{is injective}  & \iff & f ~\text{is tubular at}~ Y.
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
f ~\text{is bijective}  & \iff & f ~\text{is}~ 1\text{-regular at}~ Y.
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
For example, or more precisely, contra example,
+
For example, the function <math>f : X \to Y\!</math> depicted below is neither total at <math>Y\!</math> nor tubular at <math>Y,\!</math> and so it cannot enjoy any of the properties of being surjective, injective, or bijective.
the function f : X -> Y that is depicted below
 
is neither total at Y nor tubular at Y, and so
 
it cannot enjoy any of the properties of being
 
sur-, or in-, or bi-jective.
 
  
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  X
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 40.jpg]] || (40)
|    \  |  /    \  \  |   |    \ /
+
|}
|     \ | /      \  \ |   |    \    f
 
|     \|/        \  \|  |    / \
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  Y
 
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
  
A cheap way of getting a surjective function out of any function
+
An easy way to extract a surjective function from any function is to reset its codomain to its range.  For example, the range of the function <math>f\!</math> above is <math>Y^\prime = \{ 0, 2, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9 \}.\!</math> Thus, if we form a new function <math>g : X \to Y^\prime\!</math> that looks just like <math>f\!</math> on the domain <math>X\!</math> but is assigned the codomain <math>Y^\prime,\!</math> then <math>g\!</math> is surjective, and is described as mapping ''onto'' <math>Y^\prime.\!</math>
is to reset its codomain to its range.  For example, the range
 
of the function f above is Y'= {0, 2, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9}.  Thus,
 
if we form a new function g : X -> Y' that looks just like
 
f on the domain X but is assigned the codomain Y', then
 
g is surjective, and is described as mapping "onto" Y'.
 
  
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  X
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 41.jpg]] || (41)
|    \  |  /    \  \  |   |    \ /
+
|}
|     \ | /      \  \ |   |    \    g
 
|     \|/        \  \|  |    / \
 
o      o          o  o  o  o  o  Y'
 
0      2          5  6  7  8  9
 
  
The function h : Y' -> Y is injective.
+
The function <math>h : Y^\prime \to Y\!</math> is injective.
  
0      2          5  6  7  8  9
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o      o          o  o  o  o  o  Y'
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 42.jpg]] || (42)
|      |            \ /    |   \ /
+
|}
|       |             \    |     \    h
 
|       |            / \    |    / \
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  Y
 
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
  
The function m : X -> Y is bijective.
+
The function <math>m : X \to Y\!</math> is bijective.
  
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  X
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 43.jpg]] || (43)
|  |  |   \ /    \ /    |    \ /
+
|}
|   |  |     \      \    |     \    m
 
|   |  |    / \    / \    |    / \
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  o  Y
 
0  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.11===
 
===Commentary Note 11.11===
  
<pre>
+
The preceding exercises were intended to beef-up our &ldquo;functional&rdquo; literacy skills to the point where we can read our functional alphabets backwards and forwards and recognize the local functionalities that may be immanent in relative terms no matter where they locate themselves within the domains of relations. These skills will serve us in good stead as we work to build a catwalk from Peirce's platform of 1870 to contemporary scenes on the logic of relatives, and back again.
The preceding exercises were intended to beef-up our
 
functional literacy skills to the point where we can
 
read our functional alphabets backwards and forwards
 
and to ferret out the local functionalites that may
 
be immanent in relative terms no matter where they
 
locate themselves within the domains of relations.
 
I am hopeful that these skills will serve us in
 
good stead as we work to build a catwalk from
 
Peirce's platform to contemporary scenes on
 
the logic of relatives, and back again.
 
  
By way of extending a few very tentative plancks,
+
By way of extending a few very tentative planks, let us experiment with the following definitions:
let us experiment with the following definitions:
 
  
1.  A relative term 'p' and the corresponding relation P c X x Y are both
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
    called "functional on relates" if and only if P is a function at X,
+
|
    in symbols, P : X -> Y.
+
<p>A relative term <math>p\!</math> and the corresponding relation <math>P \subseteq X \times Y\!</math> are both called ''functional on relates'' if and only if <math>P\!</math> is a function at <math>X,\!</math> in&nbsp;symbols, <math>{P : X \to Y}.\!</math></p>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>A relative term <math>p\!</math> and the corresponding relation <math>P \subseteq X \times Y\!</math> are both called ''functional on correlates'' if and only if <math>P\!</math> is a function at <math>Y,\!</math> in&nbsp;symbols, <math>P : X \leftarrow Y.\!</math></p>
 +
|}
  
2.  A relative term 'p' and the corresponding relation P c X x Y are both
+
When a relation happens to be a function, it may be excusable to use the same name for it in both applications, writing out explicit type markers like <math>P : X \times Y,\!</math> &nbsp; <math>P : X \to Y,\!</math> &nbsp; <math>P : X \leftarrow Y,\!</math> as the case may be, when and if it serves to clarify matters.
    called "functional on correlates" if and only if P is function at Y,
 
    in symbols, P : X <- Y.
 
  
When a relation happens to be a function, it may be excusable
+
From this current, perhaps transient, perspective, it appears that our next task is to examine how the known properties of relations are modified when an aspect of functionality is spied in the mix.  Let us then return to our various ways of looking at relational composition, and see what changes and what stays the same when the relations in question happen to be functions of various different kinds at some of their domains.  Here is one generic picture of relational composition, cast in a style that hews pretty close to the line of potentials inherent in Peirce's syntax of this period.
to use the same name for it in both applications, writing out
 
explicit type markers like P : X x Y, P : X -> Y, P : X <- Y,
 
as the case may be, when and if it serves to clarify matters.
 
  
From this current, perhaps transient, perspective, it appears that
+
<br>
our next task is to examine how the known properties of relations
 
are modified when an aspect of functionality is spied in the mix.
 
  
Let us then return to our various ways of looking at relational composition,
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
and see what changes and what stays the same when the relations in question
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 44.jpg]] || (44)
happen to be functions of various different kinds at some of their domains.
+
|}
  
Here is one generic picture of relational composition,
+
From this we extract the ''hypergraph picture'' of relational composition:
cast in a style that hews pretty close to the line of
 
potentials inherent in Peirce's syntax of this period.
 
  
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
+
<br>
|                                                          |
 
|                          P o Q                          |
 
|                ____________^____________                |
 
|                /                        \                |
 
|              /      P            Q      \              |
 
|              /      @            @      \              |
 
|            /      / \          / \      \            |
 
|            /      /  \        /  \      \            |
 
|          o      o    o      o    o      o          |
 
|          X      X    Y      Y    Z      Z          |
 
|      1,__#      #'p'__$      $'q'__%      %1          |
 
|          o      o    o      o    o      o          |
 
|            \    /      \    /      \    /            |
 
|            \  /        \  /        \  /            |
 
|              \ /          \ /          \ /              |
 
|              @            @            @              |
 
|              !1!          !1!          !1!              |
 
|                                                          |
 
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 16.  Anything that is a 'p' of a 'q' of Anything
 
  
From this we extract the "hypergraph picture" of relational composition:
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 45.jpg]] || (45)
 +
|}
  
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
+
All of the relevant information of these Figures can be compressed into the form of a spreadsheet, or constraint satisfaction table:
|                                                          |
 
|                P        P o Q        Q                |
 
|                @          @          @                |
 
|                / \        / \        / \                |
 
|              /  \      /  \      /  \              |
 
|              o    o    o    o    o    o              |
 
|              X    Y    X    Z    Y    Z              |
 
|              o    o    o    o    o    o              |
 
|              \    \  /      \  /    /              |
 
|                \    \ /        \ /    /                |
 
|                \    /          \    /                |
 
|                  \  / \        / \  /                  |
 
|                  \ /  \___ ___/  \ /                  |
 
|                    @        @        @                    |
 
|                  !1!      !1!      !1!                  |
 
|                                                          |
 
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 17.  Relational Composition P o Q
 
  
All of the relevant information of these Figures can be compressed
+
<br>
into the form of a "spreadsheet", or constraint satisfaction table:
 
  
Table 18. Relational Composition P o Q
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
|+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 46.} ~~ \text{Relational Composition}~ P \circ Q\!</math>
|         #  !1!   |   !1!   |   !1!   |
+
|-
o=========o=========o=========o=========o
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | &nbsp;
|   P    #    X   |   Y   |         |
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
|   Q    #        |   Y   |   Z   |
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>\mathit{1}\!</math>
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
|-
| P o Q #    X   |         |   Z   |
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>P\!</math>
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>Q\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
| <math>Z\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>P \circ Q</math>
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>Z\!</math>
 +
|}
  
So the following presents itself as a reasonable plan of study:
+
<br>
Let's see how much easy mileage we can get in our exploration
+
 
of functions by adopting the above templates as a paradigm.
+
So the following presents itself as a reasonable plan of study: Let's see how much easy mileage we can get in our exploration of functions by adopting the above templates as a paradigm.
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.12===
 
===Commentary Note 11.12===
  
<pre>
+
Since functions are special cases of dyadic relations and since the space of dyadic relations is closed under relational composition &mdash; that is, the composition of two dyadic relations is again a dyadic relation &mdash; we know that the relational composition of two functions has to be a dyadic relation.  If the relational composition of two functions is necessarily a function, too, then we would be justified in speaking of ''functional composition'' and also in saying that the space of functions is closed under this functional form of composition.
Since functions are special cases of 2-adic relations, and since the space
 
of 2-adic relations is closed under relational composition, in other words,
 
the composition of a couple of 2-adic relations is again a 2-adic relation,
 
we know that the relational composition of a couple of functions has to be
 
a 2-adic relation.  If it is also necessarily a function, then we would be
 
justified in speaking of "functional composition", and also of saying that
 
the space of functions is closed under this functional form of composition.
 
  
Just for novelty's sake, let's try to prove this
+
Just for novelty's sake, let's try to prove this for relations that are functional on correlates.
for relations that are functional on correlates.
 
  
So our task is this:  Given a couple of 2-adic relations,
+
The task is this &mdash; We are given a pair of dyadic relations:
P c X x Y and Q c Y x Z, that are functional on correlates,
 
P : X <- Y and Q : Y <- Z, we need to determine whether the
 
relational composition P o Q c X x Z is also P o Q : X <- Z,
 
or not.
 
  
It always helps to begin by recalling the pertinent definitions.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>P \subseteq X \times Y \quad \text{and} \quad Q \subseteq Y \times Z\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
<math>P\!</math> and <math>Q\!</math> are assumed to be functional on correlates, a premiss that we express as follows:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>P : X \gets Y \quad \text{and} \quad Q : Y \gets Z\!</math>
 +
|}
  
For a 2-adic relation L c X x Y, we have:
+
We are charged with deciding whether the relational composition <math>P \circ Q \subseteq X \times Z\!</math> is also functional on correlates, in symbols, whether <math>{P \circ Q : X \gets Z}.\!</math>
  
L is a "function" L : X <- Y  iff  L is 1-regular at Y.
+
It always helps to begin by recalling the pertinent definitions.
  
As for the definition of relational composition,
+
For a dyadic relation <math>L \subseteq X \times Y,\!</math> we have:
it is enough to consider the coefficient of the
 
composite on an arbitrary ordered pair like i:j.
 
  
(P o Q)_ij  = Sum_k (P_ik Q_kj).
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
L ~\text{is a function}~ L : X \gets Y
 +
& \iff &
 +
L ~\text{is}~ 1\text{-regular at}~ Y.
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
So let us begin.
+
As for the definition of relational composition, it is enough to consider the coefficient of the composite relation on an arbitrary ordered pair, <math>i\!:\!j.</math>  For that, we have the following formula, where the summation indicated is logical disjunction:
  
P : X <- Y, or P being 1-regular at Y, means that there
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
is exactly one ordered pair i:k in P for each k in Y.
+
| <math>(P \circ Q)_{ij} ~=~ \sum_k P_{ik} Q_{kj}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
Q : Y <- Z, or Q being 1-regular at Z, means that there
+
So let's begin.
is exactly one ordered pair k:j in Q for each j in Z.
 
  
Thus, there is exactly one ordered pair i:j in P o Q
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
for each j in Z, which means that P o Q is 1-regular
+
|
at Z, and so we have the function P o Q : X <- Z.
+
<p><math>P : X \gets Y,\!</math> or the fact that <math>P ~\text{is}~ 1\text{-regular at}~ Y,\!</math> means that there is exactly one ordered pair <math>i\!:\!k \in P</math> for each <math>k \in Y.\!</math></p>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p><math>Q : Y \gets Z,\!</math> or the fact that <math>Q ~\text{is}~ 1\text{-regular at}~ Z,\!</math> means that there is exactly one ordered pair <math>k\!:\!j \in Q</math> for each <math>j \in Z.\!</math></p>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<p>As a result, there is exactly one ordered pair <math>i\!:\!j \in P \circ Q</math> for each <math>j \in Z,\!</math> which means that <math>P \circ Q ~\text{is}~ 1\text{-regular at}~ Z,\!</math> and so we have the function <math>{P \circ Q : X \gets Z}.\!</math></p>
 +
|}
  
 
And we are done.
 
And we are done.
 
Bur proofs after midnight must be checked the next day.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.13===
 
===Commentary Note 11.13===
  
<pre>
+
As we make our way toward the foothills of Peirce's 1870 Logic of Relatives, there are several pieces of equipment that we must not leave the plains without, namely, the utilities variously known as ''arrows'', ''morphisms'', ''homomorphisms'', ''structure-preserving maps'', among other names, depending on the altitude of abstraction we happen to be traversing at the moment in question. As a moderate to middling but not too beaten track, let's examine a few ways of defining morphisms that will serve us in the present discussion.
As we make our way toward the foothills of Peirce's 1870 LOR, there
 
is one piece of equipment that we dare not leave the plains without --
 
for there is little hope that "l'or dans les montagnes là" will lie
 
among our prospects without the ready use of its leverage and lifts --
 
and that is a facility with the utilities that are variously called
 
"arrows", "morphisms", "homomorphisms", "structure-preserving maps",
 
and several other names, in accord with the altitude of abstraction
 
at which one happens to be working, at the given moment in question.
 
  
As a middle but not too beaten track, I will lay out the definition
+
Suppose we are given three functions <math>J, K, L~\!</math> that satisfy the following conditions:
of a morphism in the forms that we will need right off, in a slight
 
excess of formality at first, but quickly bringing the bird home to
 
roost on more familiar perches.
 
  
Let's say that we have three functions J, K, L
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
that have the following types and that satisfy
 
the equation that follows:
 
 
 
| J : X <- Y
 
 
|
 
|
| K : X <- X x X
+
<math>\begin{array}{lcccl}
 +
J & : & X & \gets & Y
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
K & : & X & \gets & X \times X
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
L & : & Y & \gets & Y \times Y
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| L : Y <- Y x Y
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
|
+
J(L(u, v)) & = & K(Ju, Jv)
| J(L(u, v)) = K(Ju, Jv)
+
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
Our sagittarian leitmotif can be rubricized in the following slogan:
 
Our sagittarian leitmotif can be rubricized in the following slogan:
  
>->  The image of the ligature is the compound of the images.   <-<
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="12" width="90%"
 +
| <math>\textit{The~image~of~the~ligature~is~the~compound~of~the~images.}</math>
 +
|-
 +
| (Where <math>J\!</math> is the ''image'', <math>K\!</math> is the ''compound'', and <math>L\!</math> is the ''ligature''.)
 +
|}
  
Where J is the "image", K is the "compound", and L is the "ligature".
+
Figure&nbsp;47 presents us with a picture of the situation in question.
  
Figure 19 presents us with a picture of the situation in question.
+
<br>
  
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
|                                                          |
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 47.jpg]] || (47)
|                       K          L                      |
+
|}
|                      @          @                      |
 
|                      /|\        /|\                      |
 
|                    / | \      / | \                    |
 
|                    v  |  \    v  |  \                    |
 
|                  o  o  o  o  o  o                  |
 
|                  X  X  X  Y  Y  Y                  |
 
|                  o  o  o  o  o  o                  |
 
|                    ^  ^  ^ /  /  /                    |
 
|                     \  \  \  /  /                    |
 
|                     \  \ / \ /  /                      |
 
|                      \  \  \  /                      |
 
|                        \ / \ / \ /                        |
 
|                        @  @  @                        |
 
|                        J  J  J                        |
 
|                                                          |
 
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 19.  Structure Preserving Transformation J : K <- L
 
  
Here, I have used arrowheads to indicate the relational domains
+
Table&nbsp;48 gives the constraint matrix version of the same thing.
at which each of the relations J, K, L happens to be functional.
 
  
Table 20 gives the constraint matrix version of the same thing.
+
<br>
  
Table 20. Arrow: J(L(u, v)) = K(Ju, Jv)
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
|+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 48.} ~~ \text{Arrow Equation:} ~~ J(L(u, v)) = K(Ju, Jv)\!</math>
|         #    J   |   J    |   J   |
+
|-
o=========o=========o=========o=========o
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | &nbsp;
|   K    #    X   |   X   |   X   |
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>J\!</math>
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>J\!</math>
|   L    #    Y   |   Y   |   Y   |
+
| style="border-bottom:1px solid black; width:25%" | <math>J\!</math>
o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>K\!</math>
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
| <math>X\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>L\!</math>
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
| <math>Y\!</math>
 +
|}
  
One way to read this Table is in terms of the informational redundancies
+
<br>
that it schematizes.  In particular, it can be read to say that when one
+
 
satisfies the constraint in the L row, along with all of the constraints
+
One way to read this Table is in terms of the informational redundancies that it schematizes.  In particular, it can be read to say that when one satisfies the constraint in the <math>L\!</math> row, along with all the constraints in the <math>J\!</math> columns, then the constraint in the <math>K\!</math> row is automatically true. That is one way of understanding the equation:  <math>J(L(u, v)) ~=~ K(Ju, Jv).</math>
in the J columns, then the constraint in the K row is automatically true.
 
That is one way of understanding the equation:  J(L(u, v)) = K(Ju, Jv).
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.14===
 
===Commentary Note 11.14===
  
<pre>
+
Now, as promised, let's look at a more homely example of a morphism, say, any one of the mappings <math>J : \mathbb{R} \to \mathbb{R}\!</math> (roughly speaking) that are commonly known as ''logarithm functions'', where you get to pick your favorite baseIn this case, <math>K(r, s) = r + s~\!</math> and <math>L(u, v) = u \cdot v,\!</math> and the defining formula <math>J(L(u, v)) = K(Ju, Jv)\!</math> comes out looking like <math>J(u \cdot v) = J(u) + J(v),\!</math> writing a dot <math>(\cdot)~\!</math> and a plus sign <math>(+)\!</math> for the ordinary binary operations of arithmetical multiplication and arithmetical summation, respectively.
First, a correctionIgnore for now the
 
gloss that I gave in regard to Figure 19:
 
  
| Here, I have used arrowheads to indicate the relational domains
+
<br>
| at which each of the relations J, K, L happens to be functional.
 
  
It is more like the feathers of the arrows that serve to mark the
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
relational domains at which the relations J, K, L are functional,
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 49.jpg]] || (49)
but it would take yet another construction to make this precise,
+
|}
as the feathers are not uniquely appointed but many splintered.
 
  
Now, as promised, let's look at a more homely example of a morphism,
+
Thus, where the ''image'' <math>J\!</math> is the logarithm map, the ''compound'' <math>K\!</math> is the numerical sum, and the ''ligature'' <math>L\!</math> is the numerical product, one has the following rule of thumb:
say, any one of the mappings J : R -> R (roughly speaking) that are
 
commonly known as "logarithm functions", where you get to pick your
 
favorite base.  In this case, K(r, s) = r + s and L(u, v) = u . v,
 
and the defining formula J(L(u, v)) = K(Ju, Jv) comes out looking
 
like J(u . v) = J(u) + J(v), writing a dot (.) and a plus sign (+)
 
for the ordinary 2-ary operations of arithmetical multiplication
 
and arithmetical summation, respectively.
 
  
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
|                                                          |
 
|                      {+}        {.}                      |
 
|                      @          @                      |
 
|                      /|\        /|\                      |
 
|                    / | \      / | \                    |
 
|                   v  |  \    v  |  \                    |
 
|                  o  o  o  o  o  o                  |
 
|                  X  X  X  Y  Y  Y                  |
 
|                  o  o  o  o  o  o                  |
 
|                    ^  ^  ^ /  /  /                    |
 
|                    \  \  \  /  /                    |
 
|                      \  \ / \ /  /                      |
 
|                      \  \  \  /                      |
 
|                        \ / \ / \ /                        |
 
|                        @  @  @                        |
 
|                        J  J  J                        |
 
|                                                          |
 
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 21.  Logarithm Arrow J : {+} <- {.}
 
 
 
Thus, where the "image" J is the logarithm map,
 
the "compound" K is the numerical sum, and the
 
the "ligature" L is the numerical product, one
 
obtains the immemorial mnemonic motto:
 
 
 
| The image of the product is the sum of the images.
 
 
|
 
|
| J(u . v)  =  J(u) + J(v)
+
<p><math>\textit{The~image~of~the~product~is~the~sum~of~the~images.}</math></p>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| J(L(u, v)) = K(Ju, Jv)
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
</pre>
+
J(u \cdot v) & = & J(u) + J(v)
 +
\\[12pt]
 +
J(L(u, v)) & = & K(Ju, Jv)
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.15===
 
===Commentary Note 11.15===
  
<pre>
+
I'm going to elaborate a little further on the subject of arrows, morphisms, or structure-preserving maps, as a modest amount of extra work at this point will repay ample dividends when it comes time to revisit Peirce's &ldquo;number of&rdquo; function on logical terms.
I'm going to elaborate a little further on the subject
 
of arrows, morphisms, or structure-preserving maps, as
 
a modest amount of extra work at this point will repay
 
ample dividends when it comes time to revisit Peirce's
 
"number of" function on logical terms.
 
  
The "structure" that is being preserved by a structure-preserving map
+
The ''structure'' that is preserved by a structure-preserving map is just the structure that we all know and love as a triadic relation. Very typically, it will be the type of triadic relation that defines the type of binary operation that obeys the rules of a mathematical structure that is known as a ''group'', that is, a structure that satisfies the axioms for closure, associativity, identities, and inverses.
is just the structure that we all know and love as a 3-adic relation.
 
Very typically, it will be the type of 3-adic relation that defines
 
the type of 2-ary operation that obeys the rules of a mathematical
 
structure that is known as a "group", that is, a structure that
 
satisfies the axioms for closure, associativity, identities,
 
and inverses.
 
  
For example, in the previous case of the logarithm map J, we have the data:
+
For example, in the previous case of the logarithm map <math>J,\!</math> we have the data:
  
| J : R <- R (properly restricted)
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
|
 
| K : R <- R x R, where K(r, s) = r + s
 
 
|
 
|
| L : R <- R x R, where L(u, v) = u . v
+
<math>\begin{array}{lcccll}
 +
J & : & \mathbb{R} & \gets & \mathbb{R}
 +
& \text{(properly restricted)}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
K & : & \mathbb{R} & \gets & \mathbb{R} \times \mathbb{R}
 +
& \text{where}~ K(r, s) = r + s
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
L & : & \mathbb{R} & \gets & \mathbb{R} \times \mathbb{R}
 +
& \text{where}~ L(u, v) = u \cdot v
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
Real number addition and real number multiplication (suitably restricted)
+
Real number addition and real number multiplication (suitably restricted) are examples of group operations.  If we write the sign of each operation in braces as a name for the triadic relation that constitutes or defines the corresponding group, then we have the following set-up:
are examples of group operations.  If we write the sign of each operation
 
in braces as a name for the 3-adic relation that constitutes or defines
 
the corresponding group, then we have the following set-up:
 
  
| J : {+} <- {.}
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| {+} c R x R x R
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
|
+
J
| {.} c R x R x R
+
& : &
 +
[+] \gets [\,\cdot\,]
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
[+]
 +
& \subseteq &
 +
\mathbb{R} \times \mathbb{R} \times \mathbb{R}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
[\,\cdot\,]
 +
& \subseteq &
 +
\mathbb{R} \times \mathbb{R} \times \mathbb{R}
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
In many cases, one finds that both group operations are indicated by the same sign, typically &nbsp;<math>\cdot\!</math>&nbsp;, &nbsp;<math>*\!</math>&nbsp;, &nbsp;<math>+\!</math>&nbsp;, or simple concatenation, but they remain in general distinct whether considered as operations or as relations, no matter what signs of operation are used.  In such a setting, our chiasmatic theme may run a bit like these two variants:
  
In many cases, one finds that both groups are written with the same
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
sign of operation, typically ".", "+", "*", or simple concatenation,
+
| <p><math>\textit{The~image~of~the~sum~is~the~sum~of~the~images.}</math></p>
but they remain in general distinct whether considered as operations
+
|-
or as relations, no matter what signs of operation are used. In such
+
| <p><math>\textit{The~image~of~the~product~is~the~sum~of~the~images.}</math></p>
a setting, our chiasmatic theme may run a bit like these two variants:
+
|}
  
| The image of the sum is the sum of the images.
+
Figure&nbsp;50 presents a generic picture for groups <math>G\!</math> and <math>H.\!</math>
|
 
| The image of the product is the product of the images.
 
  
Figure 22 presents a generic picture for groups G and H.
+
<br>
  
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
|                                                          |
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 50.jpg]] || (50)
|                       G          H                      |
+
|}
|                      @          @                      |
 
|                      /|\        /|\                      |
 
|                    / | \      / | \                    |
 
|                    v  |  \    v  |  \                    |
 
|                  o  o  o  o  o  o                  |
 
|                  X  X  X  Y  Y  Y                  |
 
|                  o  o  o  o  o  o                  |
 
|                    ^  ^  ^ /  /  /                    |
 
|                     \  \  \  /  /                    |
 
|                     \  \ / \ /  /                      |
 
|                      \  \  \  /                      |
 
|                        \ / \ / \ /                        |
 
|                        @  @  @                        |
 
|                        J  J  J                        |
 
|                                                          |
 
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
 
Figure 22.  Group Homomorphism J : G <- H
 
  
In a setting where both groups are written with a plus sign,
+
In a setting where both groups are written with a plus sign, perhaps even constituting the very same group, the defining formula of a morphism, <math>J(L(u, v)) = K(Ju, Jv),\!</math> takes on the shape <math>J(u + v) = Ju + Jv,\!</math> which looks very analogous to the distributive multiplication of a sum <math>(u + v)\!</math> by a factor <math>J.\!</math>  Hence another popular name for a morphism:  a ''linear'' map.
perhaps even constituting the very same group, the defining
 
formula of a morphism, J(L(u, v)) = K(Ju, Jv), takes on the
 
shape J(u + v) = Ju + Jv, which looks very analogous to the
 
distributive multiplication of a sum (u + v) by a factor J.
 
Hence another popular name for a morphism:  a "linear" map.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.16===
 
===Commentary Note 11.16===
  
<pre>
+
We have enough material on morphisms now to go back and cast a more studied eye on what Peirce is doing with that &ldquo;number&nbsp;of&rdquo; function, whose application to a logical term <math>t\!</math> is indicated by writing the term in square brackets, as <math>[t].\!</math> It is convenient to have a prefix notation for the function that maps a term <math>t\!</math> to a number <math>[t]\!</math> but Peirce has previously reserved <math>\mathit{n}\!</math> for the logical <math>\mathrm{not},\!</math> so let's use <math>v(t)\!</math> as a variant for <math>[t].\!</math>
I think that we have enough material on morphisms now
 
to go back and cast a more studied eye on what Peirce
 
is doing with that "number of" function, the one that
 
we apply to a logical term 't', absolute or relative
 
of any number of correlates, by writing it in square
 
brackets, as ['t'].  It is frequently convenient to
 
have a prefix notation for this function, and since
 
Peirce reserves 'n' to signify 'not', I will try to
 
use 'v', personally thinking of it as a Greek 'nu',
 
which stands for frequency in physics, and which
 
kind of makes sense if we think of frequency as
 
it's habitual in statistics.  End of mnemonics.
 
  
My plan will be nothing less plodding than to work through
+
My plan will be nothing less plodding than to work through the statements that Peirce made in defining and explaining the &ldquo;number&nbsp;of&rdquo; function up to our present place in the paper, namely, the budget of points collected in [[Peirce%27s_1870_Logic_Of_Relatives#Commentary_Note_11.2|Section 11.2]].
all of the principal statements that Peirce has made about
 
the "number of" function up to our present stopping place
 
in the paper, namely, those that I collected once before
 
and placed at this location:
 
  
LOR.COM 11.2.  http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-November/001814.html
+
'''NOF 1'''
  
NOF 1.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 +
|
 +
<p>I propose to assign to all logical terms, numbers;  to an absolute term, the number of individuals it denotes;  to a relative term, the average number of things so related to one individual. Thus in a universe of perfect men (''men''), the number of &ldquo;tooth of&rdquo; would be 32.  The number of a relative with two correlates would be the average number of things so related to a pair of individuals;  and so on for relatives of higher numbers of correlates.  I propose to denote the number of a logical term by enclosing the term in square brackets, thus <math>[t].\!</math></p>
  
| I propose to assign to all logical terms, numbers;
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.65).</p>
| to an absolute term, the number of individuals it denotes;
+
|}
| to a relative term, the average number of things so related
+
 
| to one individual.
+
The role of the &ldquo;number&nbsp;of&rdquo; function may be formalized by assigning it a name and a type as <math>v : S \to \mathbb{R},\!</math> where <math>S\!</math> is a suitable set of signs, a ''>syntactic domain'', containing all the logical terms whose numbers we need to evaluate in a given discussion, and where <math>\mathbb{R}\!</math> is the set of real numbers.  
|
+
 
| Thus in a universe of perfect men ('men'),
+
Transcribing Peirce's example:
| the number of "tooth of" would be 32.
 
|
 
| The number of a relative with two correlates would be the
 
| average number of things so related to a pair of individuals;
 
| and so on for relatives of higher numbers of correlates.
 
|
 
| I propose to denote the number of a logical term by
 
| enclosing the term in square brackets, thus ['t'].
 
|
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.65
 
  
We may formalize the role of the "number of" function by assigning it
+
{| width="100%"
a local habitation and a name 'v' : S -> R, where S is a suitable set
+
| width="10%" | Let
of signs, called the "syntactic domain", that is ample enough to hold
+
| <math>\mathrm{m} = \text{man}\!</math>
all of the terms that we might wish to number in a given discussion,
+
| width="10%" | &nbsp;
and where R is the real number domain.
+
|-
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|-
 +
| and
 +
| <math>\mathit{t} = \text{tooth of}\,\underline{~~ ~~}.</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|-
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|-
 +
| Then
 +
| <math>v(\mathit{t}) ~=~ [\mathit{t}] ~=~ \frac{[\mathit{t}\mathrm{m}]}{[\mathrm{m}]}.\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|}
  
Transcribing Peirce's example, we may let m = "man" and 't' = "tooth of ---".
+
Thus, in a universe of perfect human dentition, the number of the relative term <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \text{tooth of}\,\underline{~~ ~~} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> is equal to the number of teeth of humans divided by the number of humans, that is, <math>32.\!</math>
Then 'v'('t') = ['t'] = ['t'm]/[m], that is to say, in a universe of perfect
 
human dentition, the number of the relative term "tooth of ---" is equal to
 
the number of teeth of humans divided by the number of humans, that is, 32.
 
  
The 2-adic relative term 't' determines a 2-adic relation T c U x V,
+
The dyadic relative term <math>t\!</math> determines a dyadic relation <math>T \subseteq X \times Y,</math> where <math>X\!</math> contains all the teeth and <math>Y\!</math> contains all the people that happen to be under discussion.
where U and V are two universes of discourse, possibly the same one,
 
that hold among other things all of the teeth and all of the people
 
that happen to be under discussion, respectively.
 
  
A rough indication of the bigraph for T
+
A rough indication of the bigraph for <math>T\!</math> might be drawn as follows, showing just the first few items in the toothy part of <math>X\!</math> and the peoply part of <math>Y.\!</math>
might be drawn as follows, where I have
 
tried to sketch in just the toothy part
 
of U and the peoply part of V.
 
  
t_1    t_32  t_33    t_64  t_65    t_96  ...    ...
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o  ...  o    o  ...  o    o  ...  o    o  ...  o    U
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 51.jpg]] || (51)
  \  |  /      \  |  /      \  |  /      \  | /
+
|}
  \ | /        \ | /        \ | /        \ | /      T
 
    \|/          \|/          \|/          \|/
 
    o            o            o            o        V
 
    m_1          m_2          m_3          ...
 
  
Notice that the "number of" function 'v' : S -> R
+
Notice that the &ldquo;number&nbsp;of&rdquo; function <math>v : S \to \mathbb{R}</math> needs the data that is represented by this entire bigraph for <math>T\!</math> in order to compute the value <math>[t].\!</math>
needs the data that is represented by this entire
 
bigraph for T in order to compute the value ['t'].
 
  
Finally, one observes that this component of T is a function
+
Finally, one observes that this component of <math>T\!</math> is a function in the direction <math>T : X \to Y,</math> since we are counting only teeth that occupy exactly one mouth of a tooth-bearing creature.
in the direction T : U -> V, since we are counting only those
 
teeth that ideally occupy one and only one mouth of a creature.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.17===
 
===Commentary Note 11.17===
  
<pre>
+
I think the reader is beginning to get an inkling of the crucial importance of the &ldquo;number of&rdquo; function in Peirce's way of looking at logic.  Among other things it is one of the planks in the bridge from logic to the theories of probability, statistics, and information, in which setting logic forms but a limiting case at one scenic turnout on the expanding vista. It is, as a matter of necessity and a matter of fact, practically speaking at any rate, one way that Peirce forges a link between the ''eternal'', logical, or rational realm and the ''secular'', empirical, or real domain.
I think that the reader is beginning to get an inkling of the crucial importance of
 
the "number of" map in Peirce's way of looking at logic, for it's one of the plancks
 
in the bridge from logic to the theories of probability, statistics, and information,
 
in which logic forms but a limiting case at one scenic turnout on the expanding vista.
 
It is, as a matter of necessity and a matter of fact, practically speaking, at any rate,
 
one way that Peirce forges a link between the "eternal", logical, or rational realm and
 
the "secular", empirical, or real domain.
 
  
With that little bit of encouragement and exhortation,
+
With that little bit of encouragement and exhortation, let us return to the nitty gritty details of the text.
let us return to the nitty gritty details of the text.
 
  
NOF 2.
+
'''NOF 2'''
  
| But not only do the significations of '=' and '<' here adopted fulfill all
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
| absolute requirements, but they have the supererogatory virtue of being very
 
| nearly the same as the common significations.  Equality is, in fact, nothing
 
| but the identity of two numbers;  numbers that are equal are those which are
 
| predicable of the same collections, just as terms that are identical are those
 
| which are predicable of the same classes.  So, to write 5 < 7 is to say that 5
 
| is part of 7, just as to write f < m is to say that Frenchmen are part of men.
 
| Indeed, if f < m, then the number of Frenchmen is less than the number of men,
 
| and if v = p, then the number of Vice-Presidents is equal to the number of
 
| Presidents of the Senate;  so that the numbers may always be substituted
 
| for the terms themselves, in case no signs of operation occur in the
 
| equations or inequalities.
 
 
|
 
|
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.66
+
<p>But not only do the significations of &nbsp;<math>=\!</math>&nbsp; and &nbsp;<math><\!</math>&nbsp; here adopted fulfill all absolute requirements, but they have the supererogatory virtue of being very nearly the same as the common significations. Equality is, in fact, nothing but the identity of two numbers;  numbers that are equal are those which are predicable of the same collections, just as terms that are identical are those which are predicable of the same classes. So, to write <math>5 < 7\!</math> is to say that <math>5\!</math> is part of <math>7\!</math>, just as to write <math>\mathrm{f} < \mathrm{m}~\!</math> is to say that Frenchmen are part of men.  Indeed, if <math>\mathrm{f} < \mathrm{m}~\!</math>, then the number of Frenchmen is less than the number of men, and if <math>\mathrm{v} = \mathrm{p}\!</math>, then the number of Vice-Presidents is equal to the number of Presidents of the Senate;  so that the numbers may always be substituted for the terms themselves, in case no signs of operation occur in the equations or inequalities.</p>
  
Peirce is here remarking on the principle that the
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.66).</p>
measure 'v' on terms "preserves" or "respects" the
+
|}
prevailing implication, inclusion, or subsumption
 
relations that impose an ordering on those terms.
 
  
In these initiatory passages of the text, Peirce is using a single symbol "<"
+
Peirce is here remarking on the principle that the measure <math>\mathit{v}\!</math> on terms ''preserves'' or ''respects'' the prevailing implication, inclusion, or subsumption relations that impose an ordering on those terms.  In these initiatory passages of the text, Peirce is using a single symbol &nbsp;<math><\!</math>&nbsp; to denote the usual linear ordering on numbers, but also what amounts to the implication ordering on logical terms and the inclusion ordering on classes. Later, of course, he will introduce distinctive symbols for logical orders.  The links among terms, sets, and numbers can be pursued in all directions, and Peirce has already indicated in an earlier paper how he would construct the integers from sets, that is, from the aggregate denotations of terms.  I will try to get back to that another time.
to denote the usual linear ordering on numbers, but also what amounts to the
 
implication ordering on logical terms and the inclusion ordering on classes.
 
Later, of course, he will introduce distinctive symbols for logical orders.
 
  
Now, the links among terms, sets, and numbers can be pursued in all directions,
+
We have a statement of the following form:
and Peirce has already indicated in an earlier paper how he would "construct"
 
the integers from sets, that is, from the aggregate denotations of terms.
 
  
We will get back to that at another time.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 +
| If <math>\mathrm{f} < \mathrm{m},\!</math> then the number of Frenchmen is less than the number of men.
 +
|}
  
In the immediate example, we have this sort of statement:
+
This goes into symbolic form as follows:
  
"if f < m, then the number of Frenchmen is less than the number of men"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{f} < \mathrm{m} & \Rightarrow & [\mathrm{f}] < [\mathrm{m}].
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|}
  
In symbolic form, this would be written:
+
In this setting the <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\!\!<\!^{\prime\prime}</math> on the left is a logical ordering on syntactic terms while the <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\!\!<\!^{\prime\prime}</math> on the right is an arithmetic ordering on real numbers.
  
f < m =>  [f] < [m]
+
The question that arises in this case is whether a map between two ordered sets is ''order-preserving''. In order to formulate the question in more general terms, we may begin with the following set-up:
  
Here, the "<" on the left is a logical ordering on syntactic terms
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
while the "<" on the right is an arithmetic ordering on real numbers.
+
| Let <math>X_1\!</math> be a set with the ordering <math><_1\!.</math>
 +
|-
 +
| Let <math>X_2\!</math> be a set with the ordering <math><_2\!.</math>
 +
|}
  
The type of principle that comes up here is usually discussed
+
An order relation is typically defined by a set of axioms that determines its propertiesSince we have frequent occasion to view the same set in the light of several different order relations, we often resort to explicit specifications like <math>(X, <_1),\!</math> <math>(X, <_2),\!</math> and so on, to indicate a set with a given ordering.
under the question of whether a map between two ordered sets
 
is "order-preserving" or notThe general type of question
 
may be formalized in the following way.
 
  
Let X_1 be a set with an ordering denoted by "<_1".
+
A map <math>F : (X_1, <_1) \to (X_2, <_2)</math> is ''order-preserving'' if and only if a statement of a particular form holds for all <math>x\!</math> and <math>y\!</math> in <math>(X_1, <_1),\!</math> namely, the following:
Let X_2 be a set with an ordering denoted by "<_2".
 
  
What makes an ordering what it is will commonly be
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
a set of axioms that defines the properties of the
+
|
order relation in question.  Since one frequently
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
has occasion to view the same set in the light of
+
x <_1 y & \Rightarrow & F(x) <_2 F(y).
several different order relations, one will often
+
\end{matrix}</math>
resort to explicit forms like (X, <_1), (X, <_2),
+
|}
and so on, to invoke a set with a given ordering.
 
  
A map F : (X_1, <_1) -> (X_2, <_2) is "order-preserving"
+
The &ldquo;number of&rdquo; map <math>v : (S, <_1) \to (\mathbb{R}, <_2)</math> has just this character, as exemplified in the case at hand:
if and only if a statement of a particular form holds
 
for all x and y in (X_1, <_1), specifically, this:
 
  
x <_1 y  =>  Fx <_2 Fy
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
 
The action of the "number of" map 'v' : (S, <_1) -> (R, <_2)
 
has just this character, as exemplified by its application to
 
the case where x = f = "frenchman" and y = m = "man", like so:
 
 
 
| f < m  =>  [f] < [m]
 
 
|
 
|
| f < m  =>  'v'f < 'v'm
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{f} & < & \mathrm{m} & \Rightarrow & [\mathrm{f}] & < & [\mathrm{m}]
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{f} & < & \mathrm{m} & \Rightarrow & v(\mathrm{f}) & < & v(\mathrm{m})
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|}
  
Here, to be more exacting, we may interpret the "<" on the left
+
Here, the <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\!\!<\!^{\prime\prime}</math> on the left is read as ''proper inclusion'', in other words, ''subset of but not equal to'', while the <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\!\!<\!^{\prime\prime}</math> on the right is read as the ordinary ''less than'' relation.
as "proper subsumption", that is, excluding the equality case,
 
while we read the "<" on the right as the usual "less than".
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.18===
 
===Commentary Note 11.18===
  
<pre>
+
An ''order-preserving map'' is a special case of a ''structure preserving map'', and the idea of ''preserving structure'', as used in mathematics, always means preserving ''some'' but not necessarily ''all'' the structure of the source domain in question.  People sometimes express this by speaking of ''structure preservation in measure'', the implication being that any property that is amenable to being qualified in manner is potentially amenable to being quantified in degree, perhaps in such a way as to answer questions like &ldquo;How structure-preserving is it?&rdquo;
There is a comment that I ought to make on the concept of
 
a "structure preserving map", including as a special case
 
the idea of an "order-preserving map".  It seems to be a
 
peculiarity of mathematical usage in general -- at least,
 
I don't think it's just me -- that "preserving structure"
 
always means "preserving 'some', not of necessity 'all',
 
of the structure in question".  People sometimes express
 
this by speaking of "structure preservation in measure",
 
the implication being that any property that is amenable
 
to being qualified in manner is potentially amenable to
 
being quantified in degree, perhaps in such a way as to
 
answer questions like "How structure-preserving is it?".
 
  
Let's see how this remark applies to the order-preserving property of
+
Let's see how this remark applies to the order-preserving property of the &ldquo;number of&rdquo; mapping <math>v : S \to \mathbb{R}.</math> For any pair of absolute terms <math>x\!</math> and <math>y\!</math> in the syntactic domain <math>S,\!</math> we have the following implications, where <math>^{\backprime\backprime}-\!\!\!<\!^{\prime\prime}</math> denotes the logical subsumption relation on terms and <math>^{\backprime\backprime}\!\!\le\!^{\prime\prime}</math> denotes the ''less than or equal to'' relation on the real number domain <math>\mathbb{R}.</math>
the "number of" mapping 'v' : S -> R.  For any pair of absolute terms
 
x and y in the syntactic domain S, we have the following implications,
 
where "-<" denotes the logical subsumption relation on terms and "=<"
 
is the "less than or equal to" relation on the real number domain R.
 
  
x -< y => 'v'x =< 'v'y
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
x ~-\!\!\!< y & \Rightarrow & vx \le vy
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
Equivalently:
 
Equivalently:
  
x -< y =>  [x] =< [y]
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
x ~-\!\!\!< y & \Rightarrow & [x] \le [y]
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
It is easy to see that nowhere near all of the distinctions that make up
+
Nowhere near the number of logical distinctions that exist on the left hand side of the implication arrow can be preserved as one passes to the linear ordering of real numbers on the right hand side of the implication arrow, but that is not required in order to call the map <math>v : S \to \mathbb{R}</math> ''order-preserving'', or what is known as an ''order morphism''.
the structure of the ordering on the left hand side will be preserved as
 
one passes to the right hand side of these implication statements, but
 
that is not required in order to call the map 'v' "order-preserving",
 
or what is also known as an "order morphism".
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.19===
 
===Commentary Note 11.19===
  
<pre>
+
Up to this point in the 1870 Logic of Relatives, Peirce has introduced the &ldquo;number of&rdquo; function on logical terms and discussed the extent to which its use as a measure, <math>v : S \to \mathbb{R}\!</math> such that <math>v : s \mapsto [s],\!</math> satisfies the relevant measure-theoretic principles, for starters, these two:
Up to this point in the LOR of 1870, Peirce has introduced the
 
"number of" measure on logical terms and discussed the extent
 
to which this measure, 'v' : S -> R such that 'v' : s ~> [s],
 
exhibits a couple of important measure-theoretic principles:
 
  
1. The "number of" map exhibits a certain type of "uniformity property",
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
    whereby the value of the measure on a uniformly qualified population
+
| valign="top" | 1.
    is in fact actualized by each member of the population.
+
| The &ldquo;number of&rdquo; map exhibits a certain type of ''uniformity property'', whereby the value of the measure on a uniformly qualified population is in fact actualized by each member of the population.
 +
|-
 +
| valign="top" | 2.
 +
| The &ldquo;number of&rdquo; map satisfies an ''order morphism principle'', whereby the illative partial ordering of logical terms is reflected up to a partial extent by the arithmetical linear ordering of their measures.
 +
|}
  
2.  The "number of" map satisfies an "order morphism principle", whereby
+
Peirce next takes up the action of the &ldquo;number of&rdquo; map on the two types of, loosely speaking, ''additive'' operations that we normally consider in logic.
    the illative partial ordering of logical terms is reflected up to a
 
    partial extent by the arithmetical linear ordering of their measures.
 
  
Peirce next takes up the action of the "number of" map on the two types of,
+
'''NOF 3.1'''
loosely speaking, "additive" operations that we normally consider in logic.
 
  
NOF 3.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 +
|
 +
<p>It is plain that both the regular non-invertible addition and the invertible addition satisfy the absolute conditions.</p>
  
| It is plain that both the regular non-invertible addition and the
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.67).</p>
| invertible addition satisfy the absolute conditions.  (CP 3.67).
+
|}
  
The "regular non-invertible addition" is signified by "+,",
+
The sign <math>^{\backprime\backprime} +\!\!, {}^{\prime\prime}</math> denotes what Peirce calls &ldquo;the regular non-invertible addition&rdquo;, corresponding to the inclusive disjunction of logical terms or the union of their extensions as sets.
corresponding to what we'd call the inclusive disjunction
 
of logical terms or the union of their extensions as sets.
 
  
The "invertible addition" is signified in algebra by "+",
+
The sign <math>^{\backprime\backprime} + ^{\prime\prime}</math> denotes what Peirce calls &ldquo;the invertible addition&rdquo;, corresponding to the exclusive disjunction of logical terms or the symmetric difference of their extensions as sets.
corresponding to what we'd call the exclusive disjunction
 
of logical terms or the symmetric difference of their sets,
 
ignoring many details and nuances that are often important,
 
of course.
 
  
| But the notation has other recommendations.  The conception of 'taking together'
+
'''NOF 3.2'''
| involved in these processes is strongly analogous to that of summation, the sum
 
| of 2 and 5, for example, being the number of a collection which consists of a
 
| collection of two and a collection of five.  (CP 3.67).
 
  
A full interpretation of this remark will require us to pick up the precise
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
technical sense in which Peirce is using the word "collection", and that will
+
|
take us back to his logical reconstruction of certain aspects of number theory,
+
<p>But the notation has other recommendations.  The conception of ''taking together'' involved in these processes is strongly analogous to that of summation, the sum of <math>2\!</math> and <math>5,\!</math> for example, being the number of a collection which consists of a collection of two and a collection of five.</p>
all of which I am putting off to another time, but it is still possible to get
 
a rough sense of what he's saying relative to the present frame of discussion.
 
  
The "number of" map 'v' : S -> R evidently induces
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.67).</p>
some sort of morphism with respect to logical sums.
+
|}
If this were straightforwardly true, we could write:
 
  
|?| 'v'(x +, y)  =  'v'x + 'v'y
+
A full interpretation of this remark will require us to pick up the precise technical sense in which Peirce is using the word ''collection'', and that will take us back to his logical reconstruction of certain aspects of number theory, all of which I am putting off to another time, but it is still possible to get a rough sense of what he's saying relative to the present frame of discussion.
|?|
 
|?| Equivalently:
 
|?|
 
|?| [x +, y]  =  [x] + [y]
 
  
Of course, things are just not that simple in the case
+
The &ldquo;number of&rdquo; map <math>v : S \to \mathbb{R}</math> evidently induces some sort of morphism with respect to logical sums.  If this were straightforwardly true, we could write:
of inclusive disjunction and set-theoretic unions, so
 
we'd "probably" invent a word like "sub-additive" to
 
describe the principle that does hold here, namely:
 
  
| 'v'(x +, y)  =<  'v'x + 'v'y
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| Equivalently:
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
? & v(x ~+\!\!,~ y) & = & v(x) ~+~ v(y) & ?
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Equivalently:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| [x +, y] =< [x] + [y]
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
? & [x ~+\!\!,~ y] & = & [x] ~+~ [y] & ?
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Of course, things are not quite that simple when it comes to inclusive disjunctions and set-theoretic unions, so it is usual to introduce the concept of a ''sub-additive measure'' to describe the principle that does hold here, namely, the following:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
v(x ~+\!\!,~ y) & \le & v(x) ~+~ v(y)
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Equivalently:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
[x ~+\!\!,~ y] & \le & [x] ~+~ [y]
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|}
  
 
This is why Peirce trims his discussion of this point with the following hedge:
 
This is why Peirce trims his discussion of this point with the following hedge:
  
| Any logical equation or inequality in which no operation but addition
+
'''NOF 3.3'''
| is involved may be converted into a numerical equation or inequality by
+
 
| substituting the numbers of the several terms for the terms themselves --
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
| provided all the terms summed are mutually exclusive. (CP 3.67).
+
|
 +
<p>Any logical equation or inequality in which no operation but addition is involved may be converted into a numerical equation or inequality by substituting the numbers of the several terms for the terms themselves &mdash; provided all the terms summed are mutually exclusive.</p>
 +
 
 +
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.67).</p>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Finally, a morphism with respect to addition, even a contingently qualified one, must do the right stuff on behalf of the additive identity:
  
Finally, a morphism with respect to addition,
+
'''NOF 3.4'''
even a contingently qualified one, must do the
 
right stuff on behalf of the additive identity:
 
  
| Addition being taken in this sense,
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
|'nothing' is to be denoted by 'zero',
 
| for then:
 
|
 
| x +, 0  = x
 
 
|
 
|
| whatever is denoted by x;  and this is the definition
+
<p>Addition being taken in this sense, ''nothing'' is to be denoted by ''zero'', for then</p>
| of 'zero'.  This interpretation is given by Boole, and
+
|-
| is very neat, on account of the resemblance between the
+
| align="center" | <math>x ~+\!\!,~ 0 ~=~ x</math>
| ordinary conception of 'zero' and that of nothing, and
+
|-
| because we shall thus have
 
 
|
 
|
| [0] = 0.
+
<p>whatever is denoted by <math>x\!</math>;  and this is the definition of ''zero''.  This interpretation is given by Boole, and is very neat, on account of the resemblance between the ordinary conception of ''zero'' and that of nothing, and because we shall thus have</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[0] ~=~ 0.</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.67
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.67).</p>
 +
|}
  
With respect to the nullity 0 in S and the number 0 in R, we have:
+
With respect to the nullity <math>0\!</math> in <math>S\!</math> and the number <math>0\!</math> in <math>\mathbb{R},</math> we have:
  
'v'0  = [0] = 0.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>v0 ~=~ [0] ~=~ 0.</math>
 +
|}
  
In sum, therefor, it also serves that only preserves
+
In sum, therefore, it can be said: &nbsp; ''It also serves that only preserves a due respect for the function of a vacuum in nature.''
a due respect for the function of a vacuum in nature.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.20===
 
===Commentary Note 11.20===
  
<pre>
+
We arrive at the last of Peirce's statements about the &ldquo;number of&rdquo; map that we singled out above:
We arrive at the last, for the time being, of
 
Peirce's statements about the "number of" map.
 
  
NOF 4.
+
'''NOF 4.1'''
  
| The conception of multiplication we have adopted is
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
| that of the application of one relation to another.  ...
 
 
|
 
|
| Even ordinary numerical multiplication involves the same idea,
+
<p>The conception of multiplication we have adopted is that of the application of one relation to another.  &hellip;</p>
| for 2 x 3 is a pair of triplets, and 3 x 2 is a triplet of pairs,
+
 
| where "triplet of" and "pair of" are evidently relatives.
+
<p>Even ordinary numerical multiplication involves the same idea, for <math>~2 \times 3~</math> is a pair of triplets, and <math>~3 \times 2~</math> is a triplet of pairs, where &ldquo;triplet of&rdquo; and &ldquo;pair of&rdquo; are evidently relatives.</p>
 +
 
 +
<p>If we have an equation of the form:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>xy ~=~ z</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| If we have an equation of the form:
+
<p>and there are just as many <math>x\!</math>'s per <math>y\!</math> as there are ''per'' things, things of the universe, then we have also the arithmetical equation:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[x][y] ~=~ [z].</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| xy  =  z
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.76).</p>
|
+
|}
| and there are just as many x's per y as there are
+
 
|'per' things, things of the universe, then we have
+
Peirce is here observing what we might call a ''contingent morphism''.  Provided that a certain condition, to be named in short order, happens to be satisfied, we would find it holding that the &ldquo;number of&rdquo; map <math>v : S \to \mathbb{R}</math> such that <math>v(s) = [s]\!</math> serves to preserve the multiplication of relative terms, that is to say, the composition of relations, in the form: <math>[xy] = [x][y].\!</math> So let us try to uncross Peirce's manifestly chiasmatic encryption of the condition that is called on in support of this preservation.
| also the arithmetical equation:
 
|
 
| [x][y]  =  [z].
 
|
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.76
 
  
Peirce is here observing what we might dub a "contingent morphism"
+
The proviso for the equation <math>[xy] = [x][y]\!</math> to hold is this:
or a "skeptraphotic arrow", if you will.  Provided that a certain
 
condition, to be named and, what is more hopeful, to be clarified
 
in short order, happens to be satisfied, we would find it holding
 
that the "number of" map 'v' : S -> R such that 'v's = [s] serves
 
to preserve the multiplication of relative terms, that is as much
 
to say, the composition of relations, in the form:  [xy] = [x][y].
 
  
So let us try to uncross Peirce's manifestly chiasmatic encryption
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
of the condition that is called on in support of this preservation.
+
|
 +
<p>There are just as many <math>x\!</math>'s per <math>y\!</math> as there are ''per'' things, things of the universe.</p>
  
Proviso for [xy] = [x][y] --
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.76).</p>
 +
|}
  
| there are just as many x's per y
+
Returning to the example that Peirce gives:
| as there are 'per' things<,>
 
| things of the universe ...
 
  
I have placed angle brackets around
+
'''NOF 4.2'''
a comma that CP shows but CE omits,
 
not that it helps much either way.
 
So let us resort to the example:
 
  
| For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
| are as many teeth to a Frenchman (perfect understood)
 
| as there are to any one of the universe, then:
 
 
|
 
|
| ['t'][f] = ['t'f]
+
<p>For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there are as many teeth to a Frenchman (perfect understood) as there are to any one of the universe, then:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[\mathit{t}][\mathrm{f}] ~=~ [\mathit{t}\mathrm{f}]</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| holds arithmetically. (CP 3.76).
+
<p>holds arithmetically.</p>
  
Now that is something that we can sink our teeth into,
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.76).</p>
and trace the bigraph representation of the situation.
+
|}
In order to do this, it will help to recall our first
 
examination of the "tooth of" relation, and to adjust
 
the picture that we sketched of it on that occasion.
 
  
Transcribing Peirce's example, we may let m = "man" and 't' = "tooth of ---".
+
Now that is something that we can sink our teeth into and trace the bigraph representation of the situation. It will help to recall our first examination of the &ldquo;tooth&nbsp;of&rdquo; relation and to adjust the picture we sketched of it on that occasion.
Then 'v'('t') = ['t'] = ['t'm]/[m], that is to say, in a universe of perfect
 
human dentition, the number of the relative term "tooth of ---" is equal to
 
the number of teeth of humans divided by the number of humans, that is, 32.
 
  
The 2-adic relative term 't' determines a 2-adic relation T c U x V,
+
Transcribing Peirce's example:
where U and V are two universes of discourse, possibly the same one,
 
that hold among other things all of the teeth and all of the people
 
that happen to be under discussion, respectively.  To make the case
 
as simple as we can and still cover the point, let's say that there
 
are just four people in our initial universe of discourse, and that
 
just two of them are French.  The bigraphic composition below shows
 
all of the pertinent facts of the case.
 
  
T_1    T_32  T_33    T_64  T_65    T_96  T_97    T_128
+
{| width="100%"
o  ...  o    o  ...  o    o  ...  o    o  ...  o      U
+
| width="10%" | Let
  \ | /      \  | /      \  | /      \  | /
+
| <math>\mathrm{m} = \text{man}\!</math>
  \ | /        \ | /        \ | /        \ | /      't'
+
| width="10%" | &nbsp;
    \|/          \|/          \|/          \|/
+
|-
    o            o            o            o          V = m = 1
+
| &nbsp;
                  |                           |
+
|-
                  |                           |         'f'
+
| and
                  |                           |
+
| <math>\mathit{t} = \text{tooth of}\,\underline{~~ ~~}.\!</math>
    o            o            o            o          V = m = 1
+
| &nbsp;
    J            K            L            M
+
|-
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|-
 +
| Then
 +
| <math>v(\mathit{t}) ~=~ [\mathit{t}] ~=~ \frac{[\mathit{t}\mathrm{m}]}{[\mathrm{m}]}.\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|}
  
Here, the order of relational composition flows up the page.
+
That is to say, the number of the relative term <math>\text{tooth of}\,\underline{~~ ~~}\!</math> is equal to the number of teeth of humans divided by the number of humans.  In a universe of perfect human dentition this gives a quotient of <math>32.\!</math>
For convenience, the absolute term f = "frenchman" has been
+
 
converted by using the comma functor to give the idempotent
+
The dyadic relative term <math>t\!</math> determines a dyadic relation <math>T \subseteq X \times Y,</math> where <math>X\!</math> contains all the teeth and <math>Y\!</math> contains all the people that happen to be under discussion.
representation 'f' = f, = "frenchman that is ---", and thus
+
 
it can be taken as a selective from the universe of mankind.
+
To make the case as simple as possible and still cover the point, suppose there are just four people in our universe of discourse and just two of them are French.  The bigraphical composition below shows the pertinent facts of the case.
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 +
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 52.jpg]] || (52)
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
In this picture the order of relational composition flows down the page. For convenience in composing relations, the absolute term <math>\mathrm{f} = \text{Frenchman}\!</math> is inflected by the comma functor to form the dyadic relative term <math>\mathrm{f,} = \text{Frenchman that is}\,\underline{~~ ~~},\!</math> which in turn determines the idempotent representation of Frenchmen as a subset of mankind, <math>F \subseteq Y \times Y.\!</math>
  
 
By way of a legend for the figure, we have the following data:
 
By way of a legend for the figure, we have the following data:
  
| = J +, K +, L +, M  = 1
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| K +, M
+
<math>\begin{array}{lllr}
 +
\mathrm{m}
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{K} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{L} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{M} \qquad = &
 +
\mathbf{1}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{f}
 +
& = & \mathrm{K} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{M}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{f,}
 +
& = & \mathrm{K}\!:\!\mathrm{K} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{M}\!:\!\mathrm{M}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathit{t}
 +
& = & (T_{001} ~+\!\!,~ \dots ~+\!\!,~ T_{032}):J & ~+\!\!,
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
&   & (T_{033} ~+\!\!,~ \dots ~+\!\!,~ T_{064}):K & ~+\!\!,
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
&  & (T_{065} ~+\!\!,~ \dots ~+\!\!,~ T_{096}):L & ~+\!\!,
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
&  & (T_{097} ~+\!\!,~ \dots ~+\!\!,~ T_{128}):M
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Now let's see if we can use this picture to make sense of the following statement:
 +
 
 +
'''NOF 4.3'''
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 
|
 
|
|'f= K:K +, M:M
+
<p>For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there are as many teeth to a Frenchman (perfect understood) as there are to any one of the universe, then:</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[\mathit{t}][\mathrm{f}] ~=~ [\mathit{t}\mathrm{f}]</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
|'t'  =  (T_001 +, ... +, T_032):J +,
+
<p>holds arithmetically.</p>
|       (T_033 +, ... +, T_064):K  +,
+
 
|       (T_065 +, ... +, T_096):L  +,
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.76).</p>
|       (T_097 +, ... +, T_128):M
+
|}
 +
 
 +
In statistical terms, Peirce is saying thisIf the population of Frenchmen is a ''fair sample'' of the general population with regard to the factor of dentition, then the morphic equation,
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>[\mathit{t}\mathrm{f}] = [\mathit{t}][\mathrm{f}],\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
whose transpose gives the equation,
  
Now let's see if we can use this picture
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
to make sense of the following statement:
+
| <math>[\mathit{t}] = \frac{[\mathit{t}\mathrm{f}]}{[\mathrm{f}]},\!</math>
 +
|}
  
| For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there
+
is every bit as true as the defining equation in this circumstance, namely,
| are as many teeth to a Frenchman (perfect understood)
 
| as there are to any one of the universe, then:
 
|
 
| ['t'][f]  =  ['t'f]
 
|
 
| holds arithmetically.  (CP 3.76).
 
  
In the lingua franca of statistics, Peirce is saying this:
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
That if the population of Frenchmen is a "fair sample" of
+
| <math>[\mathit{t}] = \frac{[\mathit{t}\mathrm{m}]}{[\mathrm{m}]}.\!</math>
the general population with regard to dentition, then the
+
|}
morphic equation ['t'f] = ['t'][f], whose transpose gives
 
['t'] = ['t'f]/[f], is every bite as true as the defining
 
equation in this circumstance, namely, ['t'] = ['t'm]/[m].
 
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.21===
 
===Commentary Note 11.21===
  
<pre>
+
One more example and one more general observation, and then we will be all caught up with our homework on Peirce's &ldquo;number of&rdquo; function.
One more example and one more general observation, and then we will
 
be all caught up with our homework on Peirce's "number of" function.
 
  
| So if men are just as apt to be black as things in general:
+
'''NOF 4.4'''
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 
|
 
|
| [m,][b] = [m,b]
+
<p>So if men are just as apt to be black as things in general,</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[\mathrm{m,}][\mathrm{b}] ~=~ [\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}],\!</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| where the difference between [m] and [m,] must not be overlooked.
+
<p>where the difference between <math>[\mathrm{m}]\!</math> and <math>[\mathrm{m,}]\!</math> must not be overlooked.</p>
|
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.76
 
 
 
The protasis, "men are just as apt to be black as things in general",
 
is elliptic in structure, and presents us with a potential ambiguity.
 
If we had no further clue to its meaning, it might be read as either:
 
  
1. Men are just as apt to be black as things in general are apt to be black.
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.76).</p>
 +
|}
  
2.  Men are just as apt to be black as men are apt to be things in general.
+
The protasis, &ldquo;men are just as apt to be black as things in general&rdquo;, is elliptic in structure, and presents us with a potential ambiguity. If we had no further clue to its meaning, it might be read as either of the following:
  
The second interpretation, if grammatical, is pointless to state,
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
since it equates a proper contingency with an absolute certainty.
+
| valign="top" | 1.
 +
| Men are just as apt to be black as things in general are apt to be black.
 +
|-
 +
| valign="top" | 2.
 +
| Men are just as apt to be black as men are apt to be things in general.
 +
|}
  
So I think it is safe to assume this paraphrase of what Peirce intends:
+
The second interpretation, if grammatical, is pointless to state, since it equates a proper contingency with an absolute certainty.  So I think it is safe to assume this paraphrase of what Peirce intends:
  
3.  Men are just as likely to be black as things in general are likely to be black.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <p>Men are just as likely to be black as things in general are likely to be black.</p>
 +
|}
  
 
Stated in terms of the conditional probability:
 
Stated in terms of the conditional probability:
  
4.  P(b|m) = P(b)
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}|\mathrm{m}) ~=~ \mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}).\!</math>
 +
|}
  
 
From the definition of conditional probability:
 
From the definition of conditional probability:
  
5.  P(b|m) = P(b m)/P(m)
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}|\mathrm{m}) ~=~ {\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}\mathrm{m}) \over \mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m})}.\!</math>
 +
|}
  
 
Equivalently:
 
Equivalently:
  
6P(b m) = P(b|m)P(m)
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}\mathrm{m}) ~=~ \mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}|\mathrm{m})\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m}).\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Taking everything together, we obtain the following result:
  
Thus we may derive the equivalent statement:
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}\mathrm{m}) ~=~ \mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}|\mathrm{m})\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m}) ~=~ \mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b})\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m}).\!</math>
 +
|}
  
7P(b m)  =  P(b|m)P(m)  =  P(b)P(m)
+
This, of course, is the definition of independent events, as applied to the event of being Black and the event of being a ManIt seems to be the most likely guess that this is the meaning of Peirce's statement about frequencies:
  
And this, of course, is the definition of independent events, as
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
applied to the event of being Black and the event of being a Man.
+
| <math>[\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}] ~=~ [\mathrm{m,}][\mathrm{b}].\!</math>
 +
|}
  
It seems like a likely guess, then, that this is the content of Peirce's
+
The terms of this equation can be normalized to produce the corresponding statement about probabilities:
statement about frequencies, [m,b] = [m,][b], in this case normalized to
+
 
produce the equivalent statement about probabilities: P(m b) = P(m)P(b).
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m}\mathrm{b}) ~=~ \mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m})\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}).\!</math>
 +
|}
  
 
Let's see if this checks out.
 
Let's see if this checks out.
  
Let n be the number of things in general, in Peirce's lingo, n = [1].
+
Let <math>N\!</math> be the number of things in general.  In terms of Peirce's &ldquo;number of&rdquo; function, then, we have the equation <math>[\mathbf{1}] = N.</math>  On the assumption that <math>\mathrm{m}\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{b}\!</math> are associated with independent events, we obtain the following sequence of equations:
On the assumption that m and b are associated with independent events,
+
 
we get [m,b] = P(m b)n = P(m)P(b)n = P(m)[b] = [m,][b], so we have to
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
interpret [m,] = "the average number of men per things in general" as
+
|
P(m) = the probability of a thing in general being a man.  Seems okay.
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
</pre>
+
[\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m}\mathrm{b}) N
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m})\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}) N
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m})[\mathrm{b}]
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = &
 +
[\mathrm{m,}][\mathrm{b}].
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
As a result, we have to interpret <math>[\mathrm{m,}]\!</math> = &ldquo;the average number of men per things in general&rdquo; as <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m})\!</math> = &ldquo;the probability of a thing in general being a man&rdquo;This seems to make sense.
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.22===
 
===Commentary Note 11.22===
  
<pre>
 
 
Let's look at that last example from a different angle.
 
Let's look at that last example from a different angle.
  
| So if men are just as apt to be black as things in general:
+
'''NOF 4.4'''
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 
|
 
|
| [m,][b] = [m,b]
+
<p>So if men are just as apt to be black as things in general,</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[\mathrm{m,}][\mathrm{b}] ~=~ [\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}],\!</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| where the difference between [m] and [m,] must not be overlooked.
+
<p>where the difference between <math>[\mathrm{m}]\!</math> and <math>[\mathrm{m,}]\!</math> must not be overlooked.</p>
|
+
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.76
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.76).</p>
 +
|}
  
In different lights the formula [m,b] = [m,][b] presents itself
+
In different lights the formula <math>[\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}] = [\mathrm{m,}][\mathrm{b}]\!</math> presents itself as an ''aimed arrow'', ''fair sample'', or ''stochastic independence'' condition.
as an "aimed arrow", "fair sample", or "independence" condition.
 
  
The example apparently assumes a universe of "things in general",
+
The example apparently assumes a universe of ''things in general'', encompassing among other things the denotations of the absolute terms <math>\mathrm{m} = \text{man}\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{b} = \text{black}.\!</math> That suggests to me that we might well illustrate this case in relief, by returning to our earlier staging of ''Othello'' and seeing how well that universe of dramatic discourse observes the premiss that &ldquo;men are just as apt to be black as things in general&rdquo;.
encompassing among other things the denotations of the absolute
 
terms m = "man" and b = "black".  That suggests to me that we
 
might well illustrate this case in relief, by returning to
 
our earlier staging of 'Othello' and seeing how well that
 
universe of dramatic discourse observes the premiss that
 
"men are just as apt to be black as things in general".
 
  
Here is the relevant data:
+
Here are the relevant data:
  
| = B +, C +, D +, E +, I +, J +, O
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| b   = O
+
<math>\begin{array}{*{15}{l}}
|
+
\mathrm{b} & = & \mathrm{O}
| m   = C +, I +, J +, O
+
\\[6pt]
|
+
\mathrm{m} & = &
| 1= B:B +, C:C +, D:D +, E:E +, I:I +, J:J +, O:O
+
\mathrm{C} & +\!\!, &
|
+
\mathrm{I} & +\!\!, &
| b, = O:O
+
\mathrm{J} & +\!\!, &
|
+
\mathrm{O}
| m, =  C:C +, I:I +, J:J +, O:O
+
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathbf{1} & = &
 +
\mathrm{B} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{C} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{D} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{E} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{I} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{J} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{O}
 +
\\[12pt]
 +
\mathrm{b,} & = & \mathrm{O\!:\!O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{m,} & = &
 +
\mathrm{C\!:\!C} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{I\!:\!I} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{J\!:\!J} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{O\!:\!O}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathbf{1,} & = &
 +
\mathrm{B\!:\!B} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{C\!:\!C} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{D\!:\!D} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{E\!:\!E} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{I\!:\!I} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{J\!:\!J} & +\!\!, &
 +
\mathrm{O\!:\!O}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
  
The "fair sampling" or "episkeptral arrow" condition is tantamount to this:
+
The ''fair sampling'' condition is tantamount to this: &ldquo;Men are just as apt to be black as things in general are apt to be black&rdquo;. In other words, men are a fair sample of things in general with respect to the factor of being black.
"Men are just as apt to be black as things in general are apt to be black".
 
In other words, men are a fair sample of things in general with respect to
 
the factor of being black.
 
  
 
Should this hold, the consequence would be:
 
Should this hold, the consequence would be:
  
[m,b] = [m,][b].
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>[\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}] ~=~ [\mathrm{m,}][\mathrm{b}].</math>
 +
|}
  
When [b] is not zero, we obtain the result:
+
When <math>[\mathrm{b}]\!</math> is not zero, we obtain the result:
  
[m,] = [m,b]/[b].
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>[\mathrm{m,}] ~=~ \frac{[\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}]}{[\mathrm{b}]}.</math>
 +
|}
  
Once again, the absolute term b = "black" is most felicitously depicted
+
As before, it is convenient to represent the absolute term <math>\mathrm{b} = \text{black}\!</math> by means of the corresponding idempotent term <math>\mathrm{b,} = \text{black that is}\,\underline{~~ ~~}.</math>
by way of its idempotent representation 'b' = b, = "black that is ---",
 
and thus it can be taken as a selective from the universe of discourse.
 
  
Here is the bigraph for the composition:
+
Consider the bigraph for the composition:
  
m,b   = "man that is black",
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b} ~=~ \text{man that is black}.</math>
 +
|}
  
here represented in the equivalent form:
+
This is represented below in the equivalent form:
  
m,b, = "man that is black that is ---".
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b,} ~=~ \text{man that is black that is}\,\underline{~~ ~~}.</math>
 +
|}
  
B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  1
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 53.jpg]] || (53)
    |          |  |  |
+
|}
    |          |  |  |   m,
 
    |           |   |  |
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  1
 
                        |
 
                        |  b,
 
                        |
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  1
 
B  C  D  E  I  J  O
 
  
Thus we observe one of the more factitious facts
+
Thus we observe one of the more factitious facts affecting this very special universe of discourse, namely:
that hold in this universe of discourse, namely:
 
  
m,b = b.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b} ~=~ \mathrm{b}.</math>
 +
|}
  
Another way of saying that is:
+
This is equivalent to the implication <math>\mathrm{b} \Rightarrow \mathrm{m}</math> that Peirce would have written in the form <math>\mathrm{b} ~-\!\!\!<~ \mathrm{m}.</math>
  
b -< m.
+
That is enough to puncture any notion that <math>\mathrm{b}\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{m}\!</math> are statistically independent, but let us continue to develop the plot a bit more. Putting all the general formulas and particular facts together, we arrive at the following summation of the situation in the ''Othello'' case:
  
That in itself is enough to puncture any notion
+
If the fair sampling condition were true, it would have the following consequence:
that b and m are statistically independent, but
 
let us continue to develop the plot a bit more.
 
  
Putting all of the general formulas and particular facts together,
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
we arrive at following summation of situation in the Othello case:
+
| <math>[\mathrm{m,}] ~=~ \frac{[\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}]}{[\mathrm{b}]} ~=~ \frac{[\mathrm{b}]}{[\mathrm{b}]} ~=~ \mathfrak{1}.</math>
 +
|}
  
If the fair sampling condition holds:
+
On the contrary, we have the following fact:
  
[m,] = [m,b]/[b] = [b]/[b] = `1`,
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>[\mathrm{m,}] ~=~ \frac{[\mathrm{m,}\mathbf{1}]}{[\mathbf{1}]} ~=~ \frac{[\mathrm{m}]}{[\mathbf{1}]} ~=~ \frac{4}{7}.\!</math>
 +
|}
  
In fact, however, it is the case that:
+
In sum, it is not the case in the ''Othello'' example that &ldquo;men are just as apt to be black as things in general&rdquo;.
  
[m,]  = [m,1]/[1]  = [m]/[1]  =  4/7.
+
Expressed in terms of probabilities:  <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m}) = \frac{4}{7}</math> and <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}) = \frac{1}{7}.</math>
  
In sum, it is not the case in the Othello example that
+
If these were independent terms we would have:  <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m}\mathrm{b}) = \frac{4}{49}.</math>
"men are just as apt to be black as things in general".
 
  
Expressed in terms of probabilities:  P(m) = 4/7 and P(b) = 1/7.
+
In point of fact, however, we have<math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m}\mathrm{b}) = \mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}) = \frac{1}{7}.</math>
  
If these were independent we'd have:  P(mb) = 4/49.
+
Another way to see it is to observe that<math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}|\mathrm{m}) = \frac{1}{4}</math> while <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}) = \frac{1}{7}.</math>
  
On the contrary, P(mb) = P(b) = 1/7.
+
===Commentary Note 11.23===
  
Another way to see it is as follows:  P(b|m) = 1/4 while P(b) = 1/7.
+
Peirce's description of logical conjunction and conditional probability via the logic of relatives and the mathematics of relations is critical to understanding the relationship between logic and measurement, in effect, the qualitative and quantitative aspects of inquiry.  To ground this connection firmly in mind, I will try to sum up as succinctly as possible, in more current notation, the lesson we ought to take away from Peirce's last &ldquo;number of&rdquo; example, since I know the account I have given so far may appear to have wandered widely.
</pre>
 
  
===Commentary Note 11.23===
+
'''NOF 4.4'''
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
Let me try to sum up as succinctly as possible the lesson
 
that we ought to take away from Peirce's last "number of"
 
example, since I know that the account that I have given
 
of it so far may appear to have wandered rather widely.
 
 
 
| So if men are just as apt to be black as things in general:
 
 
|
 
|
| [m,][b] = [m,b]
+
<p>So if men are just as apt to be black as things in general,</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[\mathrm{m,}][\mathrm{b}] ~=~ [\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}],\!</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| where the difference between [m] and [m,] must not be overlooked.
+
<p>where the difference between <math>[\mathrm{m}]\!</math> and <math>[\mathrm{m,}]\!</math> must not be overlooked.</p>
|
+
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.76
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.76).</p>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
In different lights the formula <math>[\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}] = [\mathrm{m,}][\mathrm{b}]\!</math> presents itself as an ''aimed arrow'', ''fair sampling'', or ''statistical independence'' condition.  The concept of independence was illustrated above by means of a case where independence fails.  The details of that counterexample are summarized below.
  
In different lights the formula [m,b] = [m,][b] presents itself
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
as an "aimed arrow", "fair sample", or "independence" condition.
+
| [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 53.jpg]] || (54)
I had taken the tack of illustrating this polymorphous theme in
+
|}
bas relief, that is, via detour through a universe of discourse
 
where it fails.  Here's a brief reminder of the Othello example:
 
  
B  C  D  E  I  J  O
+
The condition that &ldquo;men are just as apt to be black as things in general&rdquo; is expressed in terms of conditional probabilities as <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}|\mathrm{m}) = \mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}),\!</math> which means that the probability of the event <math>\mathrm{b}\!</math> given the event <math>\mathrm{m}\!</math> is equal to the unconditional probability of the event <math>\mathrm{b}.\!</math>
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  1
 
    |          |  |  |
 
    |          |   |  |  m,
 
    |          |  |  |
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  1
 
                        |
 
                        |  b,
 
                        |
 
o  o  o  o  o  o  o  1
 
B  C  D  E  I  J  O
 
  
The condition, "men are just as apt to be black as things in general",
+
In the ''Othello'' example, it is enough to observe  that <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}|\mathrm{m}) = \tfrac{1}{4}\!</math> while <math>\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}) = \tfrac{1}{7}\!</math> in order to recognize the bias or dependency of the sampling map.
is expressible in terms of conditional probabilities as P(b|m) = P(b),
 
written out, the probability of the event Black given the event Male
 
is exactly equal to the unconditional probability of the event Black.
 
  
Thus, for example, it is sufficient to observe in the Othello setting
+
The reduction of a conditional probability to an absolute probability, as <math>\mathrm{P}(A|Z) = \mathrm{P}(A),\!</math> is one of the ways we come to recognize the condition of independence, <math>\mathrm{P}(AZ) = \mathrm{P}(A)P(Z),\!</math> via the definition of conditional probability, <math>\mathrm{P}(A|Z) = \displaystyle{\mathrm{P}(AZ) \over \mathrm{P}(Z)}.\!</math>
that P(b|m) = 1/4 while P(b) = 1/7 in order to cognize the dependency,
 
and thereby to tell that the ostensible arrow is anaclinically biased.
 
  
This reduction of a conditional probability to an absolute probability,
+
To recall the derivation, the definition of conditional probability plus the independence condition yields <math>\mathrm{P}(A|Z) = \displaystyle{\mathrm{P}(AZ) \over P(Z)} = \displaystyle{\mathrm{P}(A)\mathrm{P}(Z) \over \mathrm{P}(Z)},\!</math> in short, <math>\mathrm{P}(A|Z) = \mathrm{P}(A).\!</math>
in the form P(A|Z) = P(A), is a familiar disguise, and yet in practice
 
one of the ways that we most commonly come to recognize the condition
 
of independence P(AZ) = P(A)P(Z), via the definition of a conditional
 
probability according to the rule P(A|Z) = P(AZ)/P(Z).  To recall the
 
familiar consequences, the definition of conditional probability plus
 
the independence condition yields P(A|Z) = P(AZ)/P(Z) = P(A)P(Z)/P(Z),
 
to wit, P(A|Z) = P(A).
 
  
 
As Hamlet discovered, there's a lot to be learned from turning a crank.
 
As Hamlet discovered, there's a lot to be learned from turning a crank.
</pre>
 
  
 
===Commentary Note 11.24===
 
===Commentary Note 11.24===
  
<pre>
+
We come to the end of the &ldquo;number of&rdquo; examples that we found on our agenda at this point in the text:
And so we come to the end of the "number of" examples
 
that we found on our agenda at this point in the text:
 
  
| It is to be observed that:
+
'''NOF 4.5'''
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 
|
 
|
| [!1!] = `1`.
+
<p>It is to be observed that</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>[\mathit{1}] ~=~ 1.</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| Boole was the first to show this connection between logic and
+
<p>Boole was the first to show this connection between logic and probabilities.  He was restricted, however, to absolute terms. I do not remember having seen any extension of probability to relatives, except the ordinary theory of ''expectation''.</p>
| probabilities.  He was restricted, however, to absolute terms.
+
 
| I do not remember having seen any extension of probability to
+
<p>Our logical multiplication, then, satisfies the essential conditions of multiplication, has a unity, has a conception similar to that of admitted multiplications, and contains numerical multiplication as a case under it.</p>
| relatives, except the ordinary theory of 'expectation'.
+
 
|
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.76 and CE 2, 376).</p>
| Our logical multiplication, then, satisfies the essential conditions
+
|}
| of multiplication, has a unity, has a conception similar to that of
 
| admitted multiplications, and contains numerical multiplication as
 
| a case under it.
 
|
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.76
 
  
There appears to be a problem with the printing of the text at this point.
+
There are problems with the printing of the text at this point. Let us first recall the conventions we are using in this transcription, in particular, <math>\mathit{1}\!</math> for the italic 1 that signifies the dyadic identity relation and <math>\mathfrak{1}</math> for the &ldquo;antique figure one&rdquo; that Peirce defines as <math>\mathit{1}_\infty = \text{something}.</math>
Let us first recall the conventions that I am using in this transcription:
 
`1` for the "antique 1" that Peirce defines as !1!_oo = "something", and
 
!1! for the "bold 1" that signifies the ordinary 2-identity relation.
 
  
CP 3 gives [!1!] = `1`, which I cannot make any sense of.
+
CP&nbsp;3 gives <math>[\mathit{1}] = \mathfrak{1},</math> which I cannot make sense of. CE&nbsp;2 gives the 1's in different styles of italics, but reading the equation as <math>[\mathit{1}] = 1,\!</math> makes the best sense if the &ldquo;1&rdquo; on the right hand side is read as the numeral &ldquo;1&rdquo; that denotes the natural number 1, and not as the absolute term &ldquo;1&rdquo; that denotes the universe of discourse. Read this way, <math>[\mathit{1}]\!</math> is the average number of things related by the identity relation <math>\mathit{1}\!</math> to one individual, and so it makes sense that <math>[\mathit{1}] = 1 \in \mathbb{N},</math> where <math>\mathbb{N}</math> is the set of non-negative integers <math>\{ 0, 1, 2, \ldots \}.</math>
CE 2 gives [!1!] = 1 , which makes sense on the reading
 
of "1" as denoting the natural number 1, and not as the
 
absolute term "1" that denotes the universe of discourse.
 
On this reading, [!1!] is the average number of things
 
related by the identity relation !1! to one individual,
 
and so it makes sense that [!1!] = 1 : N, where "N" is
 
the set or type of the natural numbers {0, 1, 2, ...}.
 
  
With respect to the 2-identity !1! in the syntactic domain S
+
With respect to the relative term <math>^{\backprime\backprime} \mathit{1} ^{\prime\prime}</math> in the syntactic domain <math>S\!</math> and the number <math>1\!</math> in the non-negative integers <math>\mathbb{N} \subset \mathbb{R},</math> we have:
and the number 1 in the non-negative integers N c R, we have:
 
  
'v'!1= [!1!] = 1.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| <math>v(\mathit{1}) ~=~ [\mathit{1}] ~=~ 1.</math>
 +
|}
  
And so the "number of" mapping 'v' : S -> R has another one
+
And so the &ldquo;number of&rdquo; mapping <math>v : S \to \mathbb{R}</math> has another one of the properties that would be required of an arrow <math>S \to \mathbb{R}.</math>
of the properties that would be required of an arrow S -> R.
 
  
The manner in which these arrows and qualified arrows help us
+
The manner in which these arrows and qualified arrows help us to construct a suspension bridge that unifies logic, semiotics, statistics, stochastics, and information theory will be one of the main themes I aim to elaborate throughout the rest of this inquiry.
to construct a suspension bridge that unifies logic, semiotics,
 
statistics, stochastics, and information theory will be one of
 
the main themes that I aim to elaborate throughout the rest of
 
this inquiry.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
==Selection 12==
 
==Selection 12==
  
<pre>
+
===The Sign of Involution===
| The Sign of Involution
+
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 
|
 
|
| I shall take involution in such a sense that x^y
+
<p>I shall take involution in such a sense that <math>x^y\!</math> will denote everything which is an <math>x\!</math> for every individual of <math>y.\!</math>&nbsp; Thus <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!</math> will be a lover of every woman.&nbsp; Then <math>(\mathit{s}^\mathit{l})^\mathrm{w}\!</math> will denote whatever stands to every woman in the relation of servant of every lover of hers;&nbsp; and <math>\mathit{s}^{(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})}\!</math> will denote whatever is a servant of everything that is lover of a woman.&nbsp; So that</p>
| will denote everything which is an x for every
+
|-
| individual of y.
+
| align="center" | <math>(\mathit{s}^\mathit{l})^\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{s}^{(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})}.\!</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| Thus
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.77).</p>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
===Commentary Note 12.1===
 +
 
 +
To get a better sense of why the above formulas mean what they do, and to prepare the ground for understanding more complex relational expressions, it will help to assemble the following materials and definitions:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="40" | <math>X\!</math> is a set singled out in a particular discussion as the ''universe of discourse''.
 +
|-
 +
| height="40" | <math>W \subseteq X\!</math> is the 1-adic relation, or set, whose elements fall under the absolute term <math>\mathrm{w} = \text{woman}.\!</math>  The elements of <math>W\!</math> are sometimes referred to as the ''denotation'' or the set-theoretic ''extension'' of the term <math>\mathrm{w}.\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| height="40" | <math>L \subseteq X \times X\!</math> is the 2-adic relation associated with the relative term <math>\mathit{l} = \text{lover of}\,\underline{~~ ~~}.\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| height="40" | <math>S \subseteq X \times X\!</math> is the 2-adic relation associated with the relative term <math>\mathit{s} = \text{servant of}\,\underline{~~ ~~}.\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="40" | <math>\mathsf{W} = (\mathsf{W}_x) = \mathrm{Mat}(W) = \mathrm{Mat}(\mathrm{w})</math> is the 1-dimensional matrix representation of the set <math>W\!</math> and the term <math>\mathrm{w}.\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| height="40" | <math>\mathsf{L} = (\mathsf{L}_{xy}) = \mathrm{Mat}(L) = \mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{l})~\!</math> is the 2-dimensional matrix representation of the relation <math>L\!</math> and the relative term <math>\mathit{l}.\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| height="40" | <math>\mathsf{S} = (\mathsf{S}_{xy}) = \mathrm{Mat}(S) = \mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{s})\!</math> is the 2-dimensional matrix representation of the relation <math>S\!</math> and the relative term <math>\mathit{s}.~\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Recalling a few definitions, the ''local flags'' of the relation <math>L\!</math> are given as follows:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| 'l'^w
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
u \star L
 +
& = & L_{u \,\text{at}\, 1}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \{ (u, x) \in L \}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \text{the ordered pairs in}~ L ~\text{that have}~ u ~\text{in the 1st place}.
 +
\\[9pt]
 +
L \star v
 +
& = & L_{v \,\text{at}\, 2}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \{ (x, v) \in L \}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \text{the ordered pairs in}~ L ~\text{that have}~ v ~\text{in the 2nd place}.
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
The ''applications'' of the relation <math>L\!</math> are defined as follows:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| will be a lover of every woman.
+
<math>\begin{array}{lll}
 +
u \cdot L
 +
& = & \mathrm{proj}_2 (u \star L)
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \{ x \in X : (u, x) \in L \}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \text{loved by}~ u.
 +
\\[9pt]
 +
L \cdot v
 +
& = & \mathrm{proj}_1 (L \star v)
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \{ x \in X : (x, v) \in L \}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
& = & \text{lover of}~ v.
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
===Commentary Note 12.2===
 +
 
 +
Let us make a few preliminary observations about the operation of ''logical involution'', as Peirce introduces it here:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 
|
 
|
| Then
+
<p>I shall take involution in such a sense that <math>x^y\!</math> will denote everything which is an <math>x\!</math> for every individual of <math>y.\!</math>&nbsp; Thus <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!</math> will be a lover of every woman.</p>
 +
 
 +
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.77).</p>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
In ordinary arithmetic the ''involution'' <math>x^y,\!</math> or the ''exponentiation'' of <math>x\!</math> to the power of <math>y,\!</math> is the repeated application of the multiplier <math>x\!</math> for as many times as there are ones making up the exponent <math>y.\!</math>
 +
 
 +
In analogous fashion, the logical involution <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!</math> is the repeated application of the term <math>\mathit{l}\!</math> for as many times as there are individuals under the term <math>\mathrm{w}.\!</math>  According to Peirce's interpretive rules, the repeated applications of the base term <math>\mathit{l}\!</math> are distributed across the individuals of the exponent term <math>\mathrm{w}.\!</math>  In particular, the base term <math>\mathit{l}\!</math> is not applied successively in the manner that would give something like &ldquo;a lover of a lover of &hellip; a lover of a woman&rdquo;.
 +
 
 +
For example, suppose that a universe of discourse numbers among its contents just three women, <math>\mathrm{W}^{\prime}, \mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime}, \mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime\prime}.</math>  This could be expressed in Peirce's notation by writing:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="60" | <math>\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathrm{W}^{\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime\prime}</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Under these circumstances the following equation would hold:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="60" | <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{l}^{(\mathrm{W}^{\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime\prime})} ~=~ (\mathit{l}\mathrm{W}^{\prime}), (\mathit{l}\mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime}), (\mathit{l}\mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime\prime}).</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
This says that a lover of every woman in the given universe of discourse is a lover of <math>\mathrm{W}^{\prime}</math> that is a lover of <math>\mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime}</math> that is a lover of <math>\mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime\prime}.</math>  In other words, a lover of every woman in this context is a lover of <math>\mathrm{W}^{\prime}</math> and a lover of <math>\mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime}</math> and a lover of <math>\mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime\prime}.</math>
 +
 
 +
The denotation of the term <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!</math> is a subset of <math>X\!</math> that can be obtained as follows:  For each flag of the form <math>L \star x\!</math> with <math>x \in W,\!</math> collect the elements <math>\mathrm{proj}_1 (L \star x)~\!</math> that appear as the first components of these ordered pairs, and then take the intersection of all these subsets.  Putting it all together:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="60" | <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w} ~=~ \bigcap_{x \in W} \mathrm{proj}_1 (L \star x) ~=~ \bigcap_{x \in W} L \cdot x</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
It is very instructive to examine the matrix representation of <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!</math> at this point, not the least because it effectively dispels the mystery of the name ''involution''.  First, let us make the following observation.  To say that <math>j\!</math> is a lover of every woman is to say that <math>j\!</math> loves <math>k\!</math> if <math>k\!</math> is a woman.  This can be rendered in symbols as follows:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="60" | <math>j ~\text{loves}~ k ~\Leftarrow~ k ~\text{is a woman}</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Reading the formula <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!</math> as &ldquo;<math>j\!</math> loves <math>k\!</math> if <math>k\!</math> is a woman&rdquo; highlights the operation of converse implication inherent in it, and this in turn reveals the analogy between implication and involution that accounts for the aptness of the latter name.
 +
 
 +
The operations defined by the formulas &nbsp; <math>x^y = z\!</math> &nbsp; and &nbsp; <math>(x\!\Leftarrow\!y) = z</math> &nbsp; for <math>x, y, z \in \mathbb{B} = \{ 0, 1 \}</math> are tabulated below:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| ('s'^'l')^w
+
<math>
 +
\begin{array}{ccc}
 +
x^y & = & z \\
 +
\hline
 +
0^0 & = & 1 \\
 +
0^1 & = & 0 \\
 +
1^0 & = & 1 \\
 +
1^1 & = & 1
 +
\end{array}
 +
\qquad\qquad\qquad
 +
\begin{array}{ccc}
 +
x\!\Leftarrow\!y & = & z \\
 +
\hline
 +
0\!\Leftarrow\!0 & = & 1 \\
 +
0\!\Leftarrow\!1 & = & 0 \\
 +
1\!\Leftarrow\!0 & = & 1 \\
 +
1\!\Leftarrow\!1 & = & 1
 +
\end{array}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
It is clear that these operations are isomorphic, amounting to the same operation of type <math>\mathbb{B} \times \mathbb{B} \to \mathbb{B}.\!</math>  All that remains is to see how this operation on coefficient values in <math>\mathbb{B}\!</math> induces the corresponding operations on sets and terms.
 +
 
 +
The term <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!</math> determines a selection of individuals from the universe of discourse <math>X\!</math> that may be computed by means of the corresponding operation on coefficient matrices.  If the terms <math>\mathit{l}\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{w}\!</math> are represented by the matrices <math>\mathsf{L} = \mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{l})</math> and <math>\mathsf{W} = \mathrm{Mat}(\mathrm{w}),</math> respectively, then the operation on terms that produces the term <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!</math> must be represented by a corresponding operation on matrices, say, <math>\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W} = \mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{l})^{\mathrm{Mat}(\mathrm{w})},</math> that produces the matrix <math>\mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}).</math>  In other words, the involution operation on matrices must be defined in such a way that the following equations hold:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="60" | <math>\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W} ~=~ \mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{l})^{\mathrm{Mat}(\mathrm{w})} ~=~ \mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w})\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
The fact that <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!</math> denotes the elements of a subset of <math>X\!</math> means that the matrix <math>\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W}\!</math> is a 1-dimensional array of coefficients in <math>\mathbb{B}\!</math> that is indexed by the elements of <math>X.\!</math>  The value of the matrix <math>\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W}\!</math> at the index <math>{u \in X}\!</math> is written <math>(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_u\!</math> and computed as follows:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="60" | <math>(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_u ~=~ \prod_{v \in X} \mathsf{L}_{uv}^{\mathsf{W}_v}\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
===Commentary Note 12.3===
 +
 
 +
We now have two ways of computing a logical involution that raises a dyadic relative term to the power of a monadic absolute term, for example, <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!</math> for &ldquo;lover of every woman&rdquo;.
 +
 
 +
The first method operates in the medium of set theory, expressing the denotation of the term <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!</math> as the intersection of a set of relational applications:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="60" | <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w} ~=~ \bigcap_{x \in W} L \cdot x\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
The second method operates in the matrix representation, expressing the value of the matrix <math>\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W}\!</math> with respect to an argument <math>u\!</math> as a product of coefficient powers:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="60" | <math>(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_u ~=~ \prod_{v \in X} \mathsf{L}_{uv}^{\mathsf{W}_v}\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Abstract formulas like these are more easily grasped with the aid of a concrete example and a picture of the relations involved.
 +
 
 +
====Example 6====
 +
 
 +
Consider a universe of discourse <math>X\!</math> that is subject to the following data:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| will denote whatever stands to every woman in
+
<math>\begin{array}{*{15}{c}}
| the relation of servant of every lover of hers;
+
X & = & \{ & a, & b, & c, & d, & e, & f, & g, & h, & i & \}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
W & = & \{ & d, & f & \}
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
L & = & \{ & b\!:\!a, & b\!:\!c, & c\!:\!b, & c\!:\!d, & e\!:\!d, & e\!:\!e, & e\!:\!f, & g\!:\!f, & g\!:\!h, & h\!:\!g, & h\!:\!i & \}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Figure 55 shows the placement of <math>W\!</math> within <math>X\!</math> and the placement of <math>L\!</math> within <math>X \times X.\!</math>
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" width="100%"
 +
| width="3%"  | &nbsp;
 +
| width="47%" | [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 55.jpg]]
 +
| width="50%" | (55)
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
To highlight the role of <math>W\!</math> more clearly, the Figure represents the absolute term <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{w} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> by means of the relative term <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{w}, \! {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> that conveys the same information.
 +
 
 +
Computing the denotation of <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!</math> by way of the set-theoretic formula, we can show our work as follows:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="60" | <math>\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w} ~=~ \bigcap_{x \in W} L \cdot x ~=~ L \cdot d ~\cap~ L \cdot f ~=~ \{ c, e \} \cap \{ e, g \} ~=~ \{ e \}</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
With the above Figure in mind, we can visualize the computation of <math>(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_u = \textstyle\prod_{v \in X} \mathsf{L}_{uv}^{\mathsf{W}_v}\!</math> as follows:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| valign="top" | 1.
 +
| Pick a specific <math>u\!</math> in the bottom row of the Figure.
 +
|-
 +
| valign="top" | 2.
 +
| Pan across the elements <math>v\!</math> in the middle row of the Figure.
 +
|-
 +
| valign="top" | 3.
 +
| If <math>u\!</math> links to <math>v\!</math> then <math>\mathsf{L}_{uv} = 1,\!</math> otherwise <math>{\mathsf{L}_{uv} = 0}.\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| valign="top" | 4.
 +
| If <math>v\!</math> in the middle row links to <math>v\!</math> in the top row then <math>\mathsf{W}_v = 1,\!</math> otherwise <math>\mathsf{W}_v = 0.\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
| valign="top" | 5.
 +
| Compute the value <math>\mathsf{L}_{uv}^{\mathsf{W}_v} = (\mathsf{L}_{uv} \Leftarrow \mathsf{W}_v)\!</math> for each <math>v\!</math> in the middle row.
 +
|-
 +
| valign="top" | 6.
 +
| If any of the values <math>\mathsf{L}_{uv}^{\mathsf{W}_v}\!</math> is <math>0\!</math> then the product <math>\textstyle\prod_{v \in X} \mathsf{L}_{uv}^{\mathsf{W}_v}\!</math> is <math>0,\!</math> otherwise it is <math>1.\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
As a general observation, we know that the value of <math>(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_u\!</math> goes to <math>0~\!</math> just as soon as we find a <math>v \in X\!</math> such that <math>\mathsf{L}_{uv} = 0\!</math> and <math>\mathsf{W}_v = 1,\!</math> in other words, such that <math>(u, v) \notin L\!</math> but <math>v \in W.\!</math>  If there is no such <math>v\!</math> then <math>(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_u = 1.\!</math>
 +
 
 +
Running through the program for each <math>u \in X,\!</math> the only case that produces a non-zero result is <math>(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_e = 1.\!</math>  That portion of the work can be sketched as follows:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="60" | <math>(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_e ~=~ \prod_{v \in X} \mathsf{L}_{ev}^{\mathsf{W}_v} ~=~ 0^0 \cdot 0^0 \cdot 0^0 \cdot 1^1 \cdot 1^0 \cdot 1^1 \cdot 0^0 \cdot 0^0 \cdot 0^0 ~=~ 1\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
===Commentary Note 12.4===
 +
 
 +
Peirce next considers a pair of compound involutions, stating an equation between them that is analogous to a law of exponents in ordinary arithmetic, namely, <math>(a^b)^c = a^{bc}.\!</math>
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 
|
 
|
| and
+
<p>Then <math>(\mathit{s}^\mathit{l})^\mathrm{w}\!</math> will denote whatever stands to every woman in the relation of servant of every lover of hers;&nbsp; and <math>\mathit{s}^{(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})}\!</math> will denote whatever is a servant of everything that is lover of a woman.&nbsp; So that</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>(\mathit{s}^\mathit{l})^\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{s}^{(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})}.\!</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| 's'^('l'w)
+
<p>(Peirce, CP 3.77).</p>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Articulating the compound relative term <math>\mathit{s}^{(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})}\!</math> in set-theoretic terms is fairly immediate:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="60" | <math>\mathit{s}^{(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})} ~=~ \bigcap_{x \in LW} \mathrm{proj}_1 (S \star x) ~=~ \bigcap_{x \in LW} S \cdot x\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
On the other hand, translating the compound relative term <math>(\mathit{s}^\mathit{l})^\mathrm{w}\!</math> into a set-theoretic equivalent is less immediate, the hang-up being that we have yet to define the case of logical involution that raises a dyadic relative term to the power of a dyadic relative term.  As a result, it looks easier to proceed through the matrix representation, drawing once again on the inspection of a concrete example.
 +
 
 +
====Example 7====
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 
|
 
|
| will denote whatever is a servant of
+
<math>\begin{array}{*{15}{c}}
| everything that is lover of a woman.
+
X & = & \{ & a, & b, & c, & d, & e, & f, & g, & h, & i\ & \}
|
+
\\[6pt]
| So that
+
L & = & \{ & b\!:\!a, & b\!:\!c, & c\!:\!b, & c\!:\!d, & e\!:\!d, & e\!:\!e, & e\!:\!f, & g\!:\!f, & g\!:\!h, & h\!:\!g, & h\!:\!i & \}
|
+
\\[6pt]
| ('s'^'l')^w  's'^('l'w).
+
S & = & \{ & b\!:\!a, & b\!:\!c, & d\!:\!c, & d\!:\!d, & d\!:\!e, & f\!:\!e, & f\!:\!f, & f\!:\!g, & h\!:\!g, & h\!:\!i\ & \}
|
+
\end{array}</math>
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.77
+
|}
|
+
 
| Charles Sanders Peirce,
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" width="100%"
|"Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives,
+
| width="3%" | &nbsp;
| Resulting from an Amplification of the Conceptions of Boole's Calculus of Logic",
+
| width="47%" | [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 56.jpg]]
|'Memoirs of the American Academy', Volume 9, pages 317-378, 26 January 1870,
+
| width="50%" | (56)
|'Collected Papers' (CP 3.45-149), 'Chronological Edition' (CE 2, 359-429).
+
|}
</pre>
+
 
 +
There is a &ldquo;servant of every lover of&rdquo; link between <math>u\!</math> and <math>v\!</math> if and only if <math>u \cdot S ~\supseteq~ L \cdot v.\!</math>&nbsp; But the vacuous inclusions, that is, the cases where <math>L \cdot v = \varnothing,\!</math> have the effect of adding non-intuitive links to the mix.
 +
 
 +
The computational requirements are evidently met by the following formula:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="60" | <math>(\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})_{xy} ~=~ \prod_{p \in X} \mathsf{S}_{xp}^{\mathsf{L}_{py}}\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
In other words, <math>(\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})_{xy} = 0\!</math> if and only if there exists a <math>{p \in X}\!</math> such that <math>\mathsf{S}_{xp} = 0\!</math> and <math>\mathsf{L}_{py} = 1.\!</math>
  
===Commentary Note 12===
+
===Commentary Note 12.5===
  
<pre>
+
The equation <math>(\mathit{s}^\mathit{l})^\mathrm{w} = \mathit{s}^{\mathit{l}\mathrm{w}}\!</math> can be verified by establishing the corresponding equation in matrices:
Let us make a few preliminary observations about the
 
"logical sign of involution", as Peirce uses it here:
 
  
| The Sign of Involution
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
|
+
| height="60" | <math>(\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})^\mathsf{W} ~=~ \mathsf{S}^{\mathsf{L}\mathsf{W}}</math>
| I shall take involution in such a sense that x^y
+
|}
| will denote everything which is an x for every
 
| individual of y.
 
|
 
| Thus
 
|
 
| 'l'^w
 
|
 
| will be a lover of every woman.
 
|
 
| C.S. Peirce, CP 3.77
 
  
In arithmetic, the "involution" x^y, or the "exponentiation" of x
+
If <math>\mathsf{A}</math> and <math>\mathsf{B}</math> are two 1-dimensional matrices over the same index set <math>X\!</math> then <math>\mathsf{A} = \mathsf{B}</math> if and only if <math>\mathsf{A}_x = \mathsf{B}_x</math> for every <math>x \in X.</math>  Thus, a routine way to check the validity of <math>(\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})^\mathsf{W} = \mathsf{S}^{\mathsf{L}\mathsf{W}}</math> is to check whether the following equation holds for arbitrary <math>x \in X.</math>
to the power of y, is the iterated multiplication of the factor x,
 
repeated as many times as there are ones making up the exponent y.
 
  
In analogous fashion, 'l'^w is the iterated multiplication of 'l',
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
repeated as many times as there are individuals under the term w.
+
| height="60" | <math>((\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})^\mathsf{W})_x ~=~ (\mathsf{S}^{\mathsf{L}\mathsf{W}})_x</math>
 +
|}
  
For example, suppose that the universe of discourse has,
+
Taking both ends toward the middle, we proceed as follows:
among other things, just the three women, W_1, W_2, W_3.
 
This could be expressed in Peirce's notation by writing:
 
  
= W_1 +, W_2 +, W_3.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
| height="200" |
 +
<math>
 +
\begin{array}{*{7}{l}}
 +
((\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})^\mathsf{W})_x
 +
& = & \displaystyle
 +
\prod_{p \in X} (\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})_{xp}^{\mathsf{W}_p}
 +
& = & \displaystyle
 +
\prod_{p \in X} (\prod_{q \in X} \mathsf{S}_{xq}^{\mathsf{L}_{qp}})^{\mathsf{W}_p}
 +
& = & \displaystyle
 +
\prod_{p \in X} \prod_{q \in X} \mathsf{S}_{xq}^{\mathsf{L}_{qp}\mathsf{W}_p}
 +
\\[36px]
 +
(\mathsf{S}^{\mathsf{L}\mathsf{W}})_x
 +
& = & \displaystyle
 +
\prod_{q \in X} \mathsf{S}_{xq}^{(\mathsf{L}\mathsf{W})_q}
 +
& = & \displaystyle
 +
\prod_{q \in X} \mathsf{S}_{xq}^{\sum_{p \in X} \mathsf{L}_{qp} \mathsf{W}_p}
 +
& = & \displaystyle
 +
\prod_{q \in X} \prod_{p \in X} \mathsf{S}_{xq}^{\mathsf{L}_{qp} \mathsf{W}_p}
 +
\end{array}
 +
</math>
 +
|}
  
In this setting, we would have:
+
The products commute, so the equation holds.  In essence, the matrix identity turns on the fact that the law of exponents <math>(a^b)^c = a^{bc}\!</math> in ordinary arithmetic holds when the values <math>a, b, c\!</math> are restricted to the boolean domain <math>\mathbb{B} = \{ 0, 1 \}.</math>  Interpreted as a logical statement, the law of exponents <math>(a^b)^c = a^{bc}\!</math> amounts to a theorem of propositional calculus that is otherwise expressed in the following ways:
  
'l'^w  = 'l'^(W_1 +, W_2 +, W_3) = 'l'W_1 , 'l'W_2 , 'l'W_3.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
(a \,\Leftarrow\, b) \,\Leftarrow\, c & = & a \,\Leftarrow\, b \land c
 +
\\[8pt]
 +
(a >\!\!\!-~ b) >\!\!\!-~ c & = & a >\!\!\!-~ bc
 +
\\[8pt]
 +
c ~-\!\!\!< (b ~-\!\!\!< a) & = & cb ~-\!\!\!< a
 +
\\[8pt]
 +
c \,\Rightarrow\, (b \,\Rightarrow\, a) & = & c \land b \,\Rightarrow\, a
 +
\end{matrix}</math>
 +
|}
  
That is, a lover of every woman in the universe of discourse
+
===Commentary Note 12.6===
would be a lover of W_1 and a lover of W_2 and lover of W_3.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
==References==
 
==References==
  
* [[George Boole|Boole, George]] (1854), ''An Investigation of the Laws of Thought, On Which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities'', Macmillan, 1854.  Reprinted, Dover Publications, New York, NY, 1958.
+
* Boole, George (1854), ''An Investigation of the Laws of Thought, On Which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities'', Macmillan, 1854.  Reprinted, Dover Publications, New York, NY, 1958.
 +
 
 +
* Peirce, C.S. (1870), &ldquo;Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives, Resulting from an Amplification of the Conceptions of Boole's Calculus of Logic&rdquo;, ''Memoirs of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences'' 9, 317&ndash;378, 26 January 1870.  Reprinted, ''Collected Papers'' (CP&nbsp;3.45&ndash;149), ''Chronological Edition'' (CE&nbsp;2, 359&ndash;429).  Online [http://www.jstor.org/stable/25058006 (1)] [https://archive.org/details/jstor-25058006 (2)] [http://books.google.com/books?id=fFnWmf5oLaoC (3)].
  
* [[Charles Sanders Peirce|Peirce, C.S.]] (1870), [[Logic of Relatives (1870)|"Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives, Resulting from an Amplification of the Conceptions of Boole's Calculus of Logic"]], ''Memoirs of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences'' 9, 317–378, 26 January 1870. Reprinted, ''Collected Papers'' (CP 3.45–149), ''Chronological Edition'' (CE 2, 359–429).
+
* Peirce, C.S., ''Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce'', vols. 1&ndash;6, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (eds.), vols. 7&ndash;8, Arthur W. Burks (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1931&ndash;1935, 1958.  Cited as (CP&nbsp;volume.paragraph).
  
==Bibliography==
+
* Peirce, C.S., ''Writings of Charles S. Peirce : A Chronological Edition'', Peirce Edition Project (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianoplis, IN, 1981&ndash;.  Cited as (CE&nbsp;volume, page).
  
* [[Charles Sanders Peirce (Bibliography)|Peirce, C.S., Bibliography]].
+
==Further Reading==
  
* Peirce, C.S., ''Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce'', vols. 1–6, [[Charles Hartshorne]] and [[Paul Weiss]] (eds.), vols. 7–8, [[Arthur W. Burks]] (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1931–1935, 1958.  Cited as (CP volume.paragraph).
+
* [[Charles Sanders Peirce (Bibliography)|Bibliography : Charles Sanders Peirce]].
  
* Peirce, C.S., ''Writings of Charles S. Peirce : A Chronological Edition'', Peirce Edition Project (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianoplis, IN, 1981–Cited as (CE volume, page).
+
* Brady, G. (2000), ''From Peirce to Skolem : A Neglected Chapter in the History of Logic'', Elsevier, Amsterdam[http://books.google.com/books?id=ahoH-tLm2S0C Online Preview].
  
==See also==
+
* Lambek, J., and Scott, P.J. (1986), ''Introduction to Higher Order Categorical Logic'', Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
  
 +
* Mili, A., Desharnais, J., Mili, F., with Frappier, M. (1994), ''Computer Program Construction'', Oxford University Press, New York, NY.
 +
 +
* Walsh, A. (2012), ''Relations Between Logic and Mathematics in the Work of Benjamin and Charles S. Peirce'',  Docent Press, Boston, MA.
 +
 +
==See Also==
 +
 +
{{col-begin}}
 +
{{col-break}}
 
* [[Charles Sanders Peirce]]
 
* [[Charles Sanders Peirce]]
 
* [[Logic of relatives]]
 
* [[Logic of relatives]]
 
* [[Logic of Relatives (1870)]]
 
* [[Logic of Relatives (1870)]]
 
* [[Logic of Relatives (1883)]]
 
* [[Logic of Relatives (1883)]]
 +
{{col-break}}
 +
* [[Relation (mathematics)|Relation]]
 +
* [[Relation theory]]
 +
* [[Sign relation]]
 +
* [[Triadic relation]]
 +
{{col-end}}
 +
 +
[[Category:Artificial Intelligence]]
 +
[[Category:Charles Sanders Peirce]]
 +
[[Category:Critical Thinking]]
 +
[[Category:Cybernetics]]
 +
[[Category:Education]]
 +
[[Category:Hermeneutics]]
 +
[[Category:Information Systems]]
 +
[[Category:Inquiry]]
 +
[[Category:Intelligence Amplification]]
 +
[[Category:Learning Organizations]]
 +
[[Category:Knowledge Representation]]
 +
[[Category:Logic]]
 +
[[Category:Logic Of Relatives]]
 +
[[Category:Logical Graphs]]
 +
[[Category:Mathematics]]
 +
[[Category:Normative Sciences]]
 +
[[Category:Philosophy]]
 +
[[Category:Pragmatics]]
 +
[[Category:Pragmatism]]
 +
[[Category:Relation Theory]]
 +
[[Category:Science]]
 +
[[Category:Semantics]]
 +
[[Category:Semiotics]]
 +
[[Category:Systems Science]]
 +
[[Category:Visualization]]

Latest revision as of 16:22, 29 December 2017

Note. The MathJax parser is not rendering this page properly.
Until it can be fixed please see the InterSciWiki version.

Author: Jon Awbrey

Peirce's text employs lower case letters for logical terms of general reference and upper case letters for logical terms of individual reference.  General terms fall into types — absolute terms, dyadic relative terms, higher adic relative terms — and Peirce employs different typefaces to distinguish these.  The following Tables indicate the typefaces that are used in the text below for Peirce's examples of general terms.


\(\text{Absolute Terms (Monadic Relatives)}\!\)

\(\begin{array}{ll} \mathrm{a}. & \text{animal} \\ \mathrm{b}. & \text{black} \\ \mathrm{f}. & \text{Frenchman} \\ \mathrm{h}. & \text{horse} \\ \mathrm{m}. & \text{man} \\ \mathrm{p}. & \text{President of the United States Senate} \\ \mathrm{r}. & \text{rich person} \\ \mathrm{u}. & \text{violinist} \\ \mathrm{v}. & \text{Vice-President of the United States} \\ \mathrm{w}. & \text{woman} \end{array}\)


\(\text{Simple Relative Terms (Dyadic Relatives)}\!\)

\(\begin{array}{ll} \mathit{a}. & \text{enemy} \\ \mathit{b}. & \text{benefactor} \\ \mathit{c}. & \text{conqueror} \\ \mathit{e}. & \text{emperor} \\ \mathit{h}. & \text{husband} \\ \mathit{l}. & \text{lover} \\ \mathit{m}. & \text{mother} \\ \mathit{n}. & \text{not} \\ \mathit{o}. & \text{owner} \\ \mathit{s}. & \text{servant} \\ \mathit{w}. & \text{wife} \end{array}\)


\(\text{Conjugative Terms (Higher Adic Relatives)}\!\)

\(\begin{array}{ll} \mathfrak{b}. & \text{betrayer to ------ of ------} \\ \mathfrak{g}. & \text{giver to ------ of ------} \\ \mathfrak{t}. & \text{transferrer from ------ to ------} \\ \mathfrak{w}. & \text{winner over of ------ to ------ from ------} \end{array}\)


Individual terms are taken to denote individual entities falling under a general term. Peirce uses upper case Roman letters for individual terms, for example, the individual horses \(\mathrm{H}, \mathrm{H}^{\prime}, \mathrm{H}^{\prime\prime}\) falling under the general term \(\mathrm{h}\!\) for horse.

The path to understanding Peirce's system and its wider implications for logic can be smoothed by paraphrasing his notations in a variety of contemporary mathematical formalisms, while preserving the semantics as much as possible. Remaining faithful to Peirce's orthography while adding parallel sets of stylistic conventions will, however, demand close attention to typography-in-context. Current style sheets for mathematical texts specify italics for mathematical variables, with upper case letters for sets and lower case letters for individuals. So we need to keep an eye out for the difference between the individual \(\mathrm{X}\!\) of the genus \(\mathrm{x}\!\) and the element \(x\!\) of the set \(X\!\) as we pass between the two styles of text.

Selection 1

Use of the Letters

The letters of the alphabet will denote logical signs.

Now logical terms are of three grand classes.

The first embraces those whose logical form involves only the conception of quality, and which therefore represent a thing simply as “a ——”. These discriminate objects in the most rudimentary way, which does not involve any consciousness of discrimination. They regard an object as it is in itself as such (quale); for example, as horse, tree, or man. These are absolute terms.

The second class embraces terms whose logical form involves the conception of relation, and which require the addition of another term to complete the denotation. These discriminate objects with a distinct consciousness of discrimination. They regard an object as over against another, that is as relative; as father of, lover of, or servant of. These are simple relative terms.

The third class embraces terms whose logical form involves the conception of bringing things into relation, and which require the addition of more than one term to complete the denotation. They discriminate not only with consciousness of discrimination, but with consciousness of its origin. They regard an object as medium or third between two others, that is as conjugative; as giver of —— to ——, or buyer of —— for —— from ——. These may be termed conjugative terms.

The conjugative term involves the conception of third, the relative that of second or other, the absolute term simply considers an object. No fourth class of terms exists involving the conception of fourth, because when that of third is introduced, since it involves the conception of bringing objects into relation, all higher numbers are given at once, inasmuch as the conception of bringing objects into relation is independent of the number of members of the relationship. Whether this reason for the fact that there is no fourth class of terms fundamentally different from the third is satisfactory or not, the fact itself is made perfectly evident by the study of the logic of relatives.

(Peirce, CP 3.63).

I am going to experiment with an interlacing commentary on Peirce's 1870 “Logic of Relatives” paper, revisiting some critical transitions from several different angles and calling attention to a variety of puzzles, problems, and potentials that are not so often remarked or tapped.

What strikes me about the initial installment this time around is its use of a certain pattern of argument that I can recognize as invoking a closure principle, and this is a figure of reasoning that Peirce uses in three other places: his discussion of continuous predicates, his definition of sign relations, and in the pragmatic maxim itself.

One might also call attention to the following two statements:

Now logical terms are of three grand classes.

No fourth class of terms exists involving the conception of fourth, because when that of third is introduced, since it involves the conception of bringing objects into relation, all higher numbers are given at once, inasmuch as the conception of bringing objects into relation is independent of the number of members of the relationship.

Selection 2

Numbers Corresponding to Letters

I propose to use the term “universe” to denote that class of individuals about which alone the whole discourse is understood to run. The universe, therefore, in this sense, as in Mr. De Morgan's, is different on different occasions. In this sense, moreover, discourse may run upon something which is not a subjective part of the universe; for instance, upon the qualities or collections of the individuals it contains.

I propose to assign to all logical terms, numbers; to an absolute term, the number of individuals it denotes; to a relative term, the average number of things so related to one individual. Thus in a universe of perfect men (men), the number of “tooth of” would be 32. The number of a relative with two correlates would be the average number of things so related to a pair of individuals; and so on for relatives of higher numbers of correlates. I propose to denote the number of a logical term by enclosing the term in square brackets, thus \([t].\!\)

(Peirce, CP 3.65).

Peirce's remarks at CP 3.65 are so replete with remarkable ideas, some of them so taken for granted in mathematical discourse that they usually escape explicit mention, and others so suggestive of things to come in a future remote from his time of writing, and yet so smoothly introduced in passing that it's all too easy to overlook their consequential significance, that I can do no better here than to highlight these ideas in other words, whose main advantage is to be a little more jarring to the mind's sensibilities.

  • This mapping of letters to numbers, or logical terms to mathematical quantities, is the very core of what "quantification theory" is all about, and definitely more to the point than the mere "innovation" of using distinctive symbols for the so-called "quantifiers". We will speak of this more later on.
  • The mapping of logical terms to numerical measures, to express it in current language, would probably be recognizable as some kind of "morphism" or "functor" from a logical domain to a quantitative co-domain.
  • Notice that Peirce follows the mathematician's usual practice, then and now, of making the status of being an "individual" or a "universal" relative to a discourse in progress. I have come to appreciate more and more of late how radically different this "patchwork" or "piecewise" approach to things is from the way of some philosophers who seem to be content with nothing less than many worlds domination, which means that they are never content and rarely get started toward the solution of any real problem. Just my observation, I hope you understand.
  • It is worth noting that Peirce takes the "plural denotation" of terms for granted, or what's the number of a term for, if it could not vary apart from being one or nil?
  • I also observe that Peirce takes the individual objects of a particular universe of discourse in a "generative" way, not a "totalizing" way, and thus they afford us with the basis for talking freely about collections, constructions, properties, qualities, subsets, and "higher types", as the phrase is mint.

Selection 3

The Signs of Inclusion, Equality, Etc.

I shall follow Boole in taking the sign of equality to signify identity. Thus, if \(\mathrm{v}\!\) denotes the Vice-President of the United States, and \(\mathrm{p}~\!\) the President of the Senate of the United States,

\(\mathrm{v} = \mathrm{p}\!\)

means that every Vice-President of the United States is President of the Senate, and every President of the United States Senate is Vice-President.

The sign “less than” is to be so taken that

\(\mathrm{f} < \mathrm{m}~\!\)

means that every Frenchman is a man, but there are men besides Frenchmen. Drobisch has used this sign in the same sense. It will follow from these significations of \(=\!\) and \(<\!\) that the sign \(-\!\!\!<\!\) (or \(\leqq\), “as small as”) will mean “is”. Thus,

\(\mathrm{f} ~-\!\!\!< \mathrm{m}\)

means “every Frenchman is a man”, without saying whether there are any other men or not. So,

\(\mathit{m} ~-\!\!\!< \mathit{l}\)

will mean that every mother of anything is a lover of the same thing; although this interpretation in some degree anticipates a convention to be made further on. These significations of \(=\!\) and \(<\!\) plainly conform to the indispensable conditions. Upon the transitive character of these relations the syllogism depends, for by virtue of it, from

  \(\mathrm{f} ~-\!\!\!< \mathrm{m}\)  

and

\(\mathrm{m} ~-\!\!\!< \mathrm{a}\)  

we can infer that

\(\mathrm{f} ~-\!\!\!< \mathrm{a}\)  

that is, from every Frenchman being a man and every man being an animal, that every Frenchman is an animal.

But not only do the significations of \(=\!\) and \(<\!\) here adopted fulfill all absolute requirements, but they have the supererogatory virtue of being very nearly the same as the common significations. Equality is, in fact, nothing but the identity of two numbers; numbers that are equal are those which are predicable of the same collections, just as terms that are identical are those which are predicable of the same classes. So, to write \(5 < 7\!\) is to say that \(5\!\) is part of \(7\!\), just as to write \(\mathrm{f} < \mathrm{m}~\!\) is to say that Frenchmen are part of men. Indeed, if \(\mathrm{f} < \mathrm{m}~\!\), then the number of Frenchmen is less than the number of men, and if \(\mathrm{v} = \mathrm{p}\!\), then the number of Vice-Presidents is equal to the number of Presidents of the Senate; so that the numbers may always be substituted for the terms themselves, in case no signs of operation occur in the equations or inequalities.

(Peirce, CP 3.66).

The quantifier mapping from terms to their numbers that Peirce signifies by means of the square bracket notation \([t]\!\) has one of its principal uses in providing a basis for the computation of frequencies, probabilities, and all of the other statistical measures that can be constructed from these, and thus in affording what may be called a principle of correspondence between probability theory and its limiting case in the forms of logic.

This brings us once again to the relativity of contingency and necessity, as one way of approaching necessity is through the avenue of probability, describing necessity as a probability of 1, but the whole apparatus of probability theory only figures in if it is cast against the backdrop of probability space axioms, the reference class of distributions, and the sample space that we cannot help but to abduce upon the scene of observations. Aye, there's the snake eyes. And with them we can see that there is always an irreducible quantum of facticity to all our necessities. More plainly spoken, it takes a fairly complex conceptual infrastructure just to begin speaking of probabilities, and this setting can only be set up by means of abductive, fallible, hypothetical, and inherently risky mental acts.

Pragmatic thinking is the logic of abduction, which is just another way of saying that it addresses the question: “What may be hoped?” We have to face the possibility that it may be just as impossible to speak of “absolute identity” with any hope of making practical philosophical sense as it is to speak of “absolute simultaneity” with any hope of making operational physical sense.

Selection 4

The Signs for Addition

The sign of addition is taken by Boole so that

\(x + y\!\)

denotes everything denoted by \(x\!\), and, besides, everything denoted by \(y\!\).

Thus

\(\mathrm{m} + \mathrm{w}~\!\)

denotes all men, and, besides, all women.

This signification for this sign is needed for connecting the notation of logic with that of the theory of probabilities. But if there is anything which is denoted by both terms of the sum, the latter no longer stands for any logical term on account of its implying that the objects denoted by one term are to be taken besides the objects denoted by the other.

For example,

\(\mathrm{f} + \mathrm{u}\!\)

means all Frenchmen besides all violinists, and, therefore, considered as a logical term, implies that all French violinists are besides themselves.

For this reason alone, in a paper which is published in the Proceedings of the Academy for March 17, 1867, I preferred to take as the regular addition of logic a non-invertible process, such that

\(\mathrm{m} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{b}\)

stands for all men and black things, without any implication that the black things are to be taken besides the men; and the study of the logic of relatives has supplied me with other weighty reasons for the same determination.

Since the publication of that paper, I have found that Mr. W. Stanley Jevons, in a tract called Pure Logic, or the Logic of Quality [1864], had anticipated me in substituting the same operation for Boole's addition, although he rejects Boole's operation entirely and writes the new one with a  \(+\!\)  sign while withholding from it the name of addition.

It is plain that both the regular non-invertible addition and the invertible addition satisfy the absolute conditions. But the notation has other recommendations. The conception of taking together involved in these processes is strongly analogous to that of summation, the sum of 2 and 5, for example, being the number of a collection which consists of a collection of two and a collection of five. Any logical equation or inequality in which no operation but addition is involved may be converted into a numerical equation or inequality by substituting the numbers of the several terms for the terms themselves — provided all the terms summed are mutually exclusive.

Addition being taken in this sense, nothing is to be denoted by zero, for then

\(x ~+\!\!,~ 0 ~=~ x\)

whatever is denoted by \(x\!\); and this is the definition of zero. This interpretation is given by Boole, and is very neat, on account of the resemblance between the ordinary conception of zero and that of nothing, and because we shall thus have

\([0] ~=~ 0.\)

(Peirce, CP 3.67).

A wealth of issues arises here that I hope to take up in depth at a later point, but for the moment I shall be able to mention only the barest sample of them in passing.

The two papers that precede this one in CP 3 are Peirce's papers of March and September 1867 in the Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, titled “On an Improvement in Boole's Calculus of Logic” and “Upon the Logic of Mathematics”, respectively. Among other things, these two papers provide us with further clues about the motivating considerations that brought Peirce to introduce the “number of a term” function, signified here by square brackets. I have already quoted from the “Logic of Mathematics” paper in a related connection. Here are the links to those excerpts:

Limited Mark Universes
(1)
(2)
(3)

In setting up a correspondence between “letters” and “numbers”, Peirce constructs a structure-preserving map from a logical domain to a numerical domain. That he does this deliberately is evidenced by the care that he takes with the conditions under which the chosen aspects of structure are preserved, along with his recognition of the critical fact that zeroes are preserved by the mapping.

Incidentally, Peirce appears to have an inkling of the problems that would later be caused by using the plus sign for inclusive disjunction, but his advice was overridden by the dialects of applied logic that developed in various communities, retarding the exchange of information among engineering, mathematical, and philosophical specialties all throughout the subsequent century.

Selection 5

The Signs for Multiplication

I shall adopt for the conception of multiplication the application of a relation, in such a way that, for example, \(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w}~\!\) shall denote whatever is lover of a woman. This notation is the same as that used by Mr. De Morgan, although he appears not to have had multiplication in his mind.

\(\mathit{s}(\mathrm{m} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{w})\) will, then, denote whatever is servant of anything of the class composed of men and women taken together. So that:

\(\mathit{s}(\mathrm{m} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{w}) ~=~ \mathit{s}\mathrm{m} ~+\!\!,~ \mathit{s}\mathrm{w}.\)

\((\mathit{l} ~+\!\!,~ \mathit{s})\mathrm{w}\) will denote whatever is lover or servant to a woman, and:

\((\mathit{l} ~+\!\!,~ \mathit{s})\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{l}\mathrm{w} ~+\!\!,~ \mathit{s}\mathrm{w}.\)

\((\mathit{s}\mathit{l})\mathrm{w}\!\) will denote whatever stands to a woman in the relation of servant of a lover, and:

\((\mathit{s}\mathit{l})\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{s}(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w}).\)

Thus all the absolute conditions of multiplication are satisfied.

The term “identical with ——” is a unity for this multiplication. That is to say, if we denote “identical with ——” by \(\mathit{1}\!\) we have:

\(x \mathit{1} ~=~ x ~ ,\)

whatever relative term \(x\!\) may be. For what is a lover of something identical with anything, is the same as a lover of that thing.

(Peirce, CP 3.68).

Peirce in 1870 is five years down the road from the Peirce of 1865–1866 who lectured extensively on the role of sign relations in the logic of scientific inquiry, articulating their involvement in the three types of inference, and inventing the concept of “information” to explain what it is that signs convey in the process. By this time, then, the semiotic or sign relational approach to logic is so implicit in his way of working that he does not always take the trouble to point out its distinctive features at each and every turn. So let's take a moment to draw out a few of these characters.

Sign relations, like any brand of non-trivial 3-adic relations, can become overwhelming to think about once the cardinality of the object, sign, and interpretant domains or the complexity of the relation itself ascends beyond the simplest examples. Furthermore, most of the strategies that we would normally use to control the complexity, like neglecting one of the domains, in effect, projecting the 3-adic sign relation onto one of its 2-adic faces, or focusing on a single ordered triple of the form \((o, s, i)\!\) at a time, can result in our receiving a distorted impression of the sign relation's true nature and structure.

I find that it helps me to draw, or at least to imagine drawing, diagrams of the following form, where I can keep tabs on what's an object, what's a sign, and what's an interpretant sign, for a selected set of sign-relational triples.

Here is how I would picture Peirce's example of equivalent terms, \(\mathrm{v} = \mathrm{p},\!\) where \({}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{v} {}^{\prime\prime}\!\) denotes the Vice-President of the United States, and \({}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{p} {}^{\prime\prime}\!\) denotes the President of the Senate of the United States.

LOR 1870 Figure 1.jpg
\(\text{Figure 1}~\!\)

Depending on whether we interpret the terms \({}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{v} {}^{\prime\prime}\!\) and \({}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{p} {}^{\prime\prime}\!\) as applying to persons who hold these offices at one particular time or as applying to all those persons who have held these offices over an extended period of history, their denotations may be either singular of plural, respectively.

As a shortcut technique for indicating general denotations or plural referents, I will use the elliptic convention that represents these by means of figures like “o o o” or “o … o”, placed at the object ends of sign relational triads.

For a more complex example, here is how I would picture Peirce's example of an equivalence between terms that comes about by applying one of the distributive laws, for relative multiplication over absolute summation.

LOR 1870 Figure 2.jpg
\(\text{Figure 2}\!\)

Selection 6

The Signs for Multiplication (cont.)

A conjugative term like giver naturally requires two correlates, one denoting the thing given, the other the recipient of the gift.

We must be able to distinguish, in our notation, the giver of \(\mathrm{A}\!\) to \(\mathrm{B}\!\) from the giver to \(\mathrm{A}\!\) of \(\mathrm{B}\!\), and, therefore, I suppose the signification of the letter equivalent to such a relative to distinguish the correlates as first, second, third, etc., so that “giver of —— to ——” and “giver to —— of ——” will be expressed by different letters.

Let \(\mathfrak{g}\) denote the latter of these conjugative terms. Then, the correlates or multiplicands of this multiplier cannot all stand directly after it, as is usual in multiplication, but may be ranged after it in regular order, so that:

\(\mathfrak{g}\mathit{x}\mathit{y}\)

will denote a giver to \(\mathit{x}\!\) of \(\mathit{y}\!\).

But according to the notation, \(\mathit{x}\!\) here multiplies \(\mathit{y}\!\), so that if we put for \(\mathit{x}\!\) owner (\(\mathit{o}\!\)), and for \(\mathit{y}\!\) horse (\(\mathrm{h}\!\)),

\(\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}\)

appears to denote the giver of a horse to an owner of a horse. But let the individual horses be \(\mathrm{H}, \mathrm{H}^{\prime}, \mathrm{H}^{\prime\prime}\), etc.

Then:

\(\mathrm{h} ~=~ \mathrm{H} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{H}^{\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{H}^{\prime\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \text{etc.}\)
\(\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h} ~=~ \mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}(\mathrm{H} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{H}^{\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{H}^{\prime\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \text{etc.}) ~=~ \mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{H} ~+\!\!,~ \mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{H}^{\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{H}^{\prime\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \text{etc.}\)

Now this last member must be interpreted as a giver of a horse to the owner of that horse, and this, therefore must be the interpretation of \(\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}\). This is always very important. A term multiplied by two relatives shows that the same individual is in the two relations.

If we attempt to express the giver of a horse to a lover of a woman, and for that purpose write:

\(\mathfrak{g}\mathit{l}\mathrm{w}\mathrm{h}\),

we have written giver of a woman to a lover of her, and if we add brackets, thus,

\(\mathfrak{g}(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})\mathrm{h}\),

we abandon the associative principle of multiplication.

A little reflection will show that the associative principle must in some form or other be abandoned at this point. But while this principle is sometimes falsified, it oftener holds, and a notation must be adopted which will show of itself when it holds. We already see that we cannot express multiplication by writing the multiplicand directly after the multiplier; let us then affix subjacent numbers after letters to show where their correlates are to be found. The first number shall denote how many factors must be counted from left to right to reach the first correlate, the second how many more must be counted to reach the second, and so on.

Then, the giver of a horse to a lover of a woman may be written:

\(\mathfrak{g}_{12} \mathit{l}_1 \mathrm{w} \mathrm{h} ~=~ \mathfrak{g}_{11} \mathit{l}_2 \mathrm{h} \mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathfrak{g}_{2(-1)} \mathrm{h} \mathit{l}_1 \mathrm{w}\).

Of course a negative number indicates that the former correlate follows the latter by the corresponding positive number.

A subjacent zero makes the term itself the correlate.

Thus,

\(\mathit{l}_0\!\)

denotes the lover of that lover or the lover of himself, just as \(\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}\) denotes that the horse is given to the owner of itself, for to make a term doubly a correlate is, by the distributive principle, to make each individual doubly a correlate, so that:

\(\mathit{l}_0 ~=~ \mathit{L}_0 ~+\!\!,~ \mathit{L}_0^{\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathit{L}_0^{\prime\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \text{etc.}\)

A subjacent sign of infinity may indicate that the correlate is indeterminate, so that:

\(\mathit{l}_\infty\)

will denote a lover of something. We shall have some confirmation of this presently.

If the last subjacent number is a one it may be omitted. Thus we shall have:

\(\mathit{l}_1 ~=~ \mathit{l}\),
\(\mathfrak{g}_{11} ~=~ \mathfrak{g}_1 ~=~ \mathfrak{g}\).

This enables us to retain our former expressions \(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w}~\!\), \(\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}\), etc.

(Peirce, CP 3.69–70).

Comment : Sets as Logical Sums

Peirce's way of representing sets as logical sums may seem archaic, but it is quite often used, and is actually the tool of choice in many branches of algebra, combinatorics, computing, and statistics to this very day.

Peirce's application to logic is fairly novel, and the degree of his elaboration of the logic of relative terms is certainly original with him, but this particular genre of representation, commonly going under the handle of generating functions, goes way back, well before anyone thought to stick a flag in set theory as a separate territory or to try to fence off our native possessions of it with expressly decreed axioms. And back in the days when a computer was just a person who computed, before we had the sorts of electronic register machines that we take so much for granted today, mathematicians were constantly using generating functions as a rough and ready type of addressable memory to sort, store, and keep track of their accounts of a wide variety of formal objects of thought.

Let us look at a few simple examples of generating functions, much as I encountered them during my own first adventures in the Fair Land Of Combinatoria.

Suppose that we are given a set of three elements, say, \(\{ a, b, c \},\!\) and we are asked to find all the ways of choosing a subset from this collection.

We can represent this problem setup as the problem of computing the following product:

\((1 + a)(1 + b)(1 + c).\!\)

The factor \((1 + a)\!\) represents the option that we have, in choosing a subset of \(\{ a, b, c \},\!\) to leave the element \(a\!\) out (signified by the \(1\!\)), or else to include it (signified by the \(a\!\)), and likewise for the other elements \(b\!\) and \(c\!\) in their turns.

Probably on account of all those years I flippered away playing the oldtime pinball machines, I tend to imagine a product like this being displayed in a vertical array:

\(\begin{matrix} (1 ~+~ a) \\ (1 ~+~ b) \\ (1 ~+~ c) \end{matrix}\)

I picture this as a playboard with six bumpers, the ball chuting down the board in such a career that it strikes exactly one of the two bumpers on each and every one of the three levels.

So a trajectory of the ball where it hits the \(a\!\) bumper on the 1st level, hits the \(1\!\) bumper on the 2nd level, hits the \(c\!\) bumper on the 3rd level, and then exits the board, represents a single term in the desired product and corresponds to the subset \(\{ a, c \}.\!\)

Multiplying out the product \((1 + a)(1 + b)(1 + c),\!\) one obtains:

\(\begin{array}{*{15}{c}} 1 & + & a & + & b & + & c & + & ab & + & ac & + & bc & + & abc. \end{array}\)

And this informs us that the subsets of choice are:

\(\begin{matrix} \varnothing, & \{ a \}, & \{ b \}, & \{ c \}, & \{ a, b \}, & \{ a, c \}, & \{ b, c \}, & \{ a, b, c \}. \end{matrix}\)

Selection 7

The Signs for Multiplication (cont.)

The associative principle does not hold in this counting of factors. Because it does not hold, these subjacent numbers are frequently inconvenient in practice, and I therefore use also another mode of showing where the correlate of a term is to be found. This is by means of the marks of reference, \(\dagger ~ \ddagger ~ \parallel ~ \S ~ \P\), which are placed subjacent to the relative term and before and above the correlate. Thus, giver of a horse to a lover of a woman may be written:

\(\mathfrak{g}_{\dagger\ddagger} \, ^\dagger\mathit{l}_\parallel \, ^\parallel\mathrm{w} \, ^\ddagger\mathrm{h}\)

The asterisk I use exclusively to refer to the last correlate of the last relative of the algebraic term.

Now, considering the order of multiplication to be: — a term, a correlate of it, a correlate of that correlate, etc. — there is no violation of the associative principle. The only violations of it in this mode of notation are that in thus passing from relative to correlate, we skip about among the factors in an irregular manner, and that we cannot substitute in such an expression as \(\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}\) a single letter for \(\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}.\!\)

I would suggest that such a notation may be found useful in treating other cases of non-associative multiplication. By comparing this with what was said above [in CP 3.55] concerning functional multiplication, it appears that multiplication by a conjugative term is functional, and that the letter denoting such a term is a symbol of operation. I am therefore using two alphabets, the Greek and Kennerly, where only one was necessary. But it is convenient to use both.

(Peirce, CP 3.71–72).

Comment : Proto-Graphical Syntax

It is clear from our last excerpt that Peirce is already on the verge of a graphical syntax for the logic of relatives. Indeed, it seems likely that he had already reached this point in his own thinking.

For instance, it seems quite impossible to read his last variation on the theme of a “giver of a horse to a lover of a woman” without drawing lines of identity to connect up the corresponding marks of reference, like this:

LOR 1870 Figure 3.jpg (3)

Selection 8

The Signs for Multiplication (cont.)

Thus far, we have considered the multiplication of relative terms only. Since our conception of multiplication is the application of a relation, we can only multiply absolute terms by considering them as relatives.

Now the absolute term “man” is really exactly equivalent to the relative term “man that is ——”, and so with any other. I shall write a comma after any absolute term to show that it is so regarded as a relative term.

Then “man that is black” will be written:

\(\mathrm{m},\!\mathrm{b}\!\)

But not only may any absolute term be thus regarded as a relative term, but any relative term may in the same way be regarded as a relative with one correlate more. It is convenient to take this additional correlate as the first one.

Then:

\(\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w}\)

will denote a lover of a woman that is a servant of that woman.

The comma here after \(\mathit{l}\!\) should not be considered as altering at all the meaning of \(\mathit{l}\!\), but as only a subjacent sign, serving to alter the arrangement of the correlates.

In point of fact, since a comma may be added in this way to any relative term, it may be added to one of these very relatives formed by a comma, and thus by the addition of two commas an absolute term becomes a relative of two correlates.

So:

\(\mathrm{m},\!,\!\mathrm{b},\!\mathrm{r}\)

interpreted like

\(\mathfrak{g}\mathit{o}\mathrm{h}\)

means a man that is a rich individual and is a black that is that rich individual.

But this has no other meaning than:

\(\mathrm{m},\!\mathrm{b},\!\mathrm{r}\)

or a man that is a black that is rich.

Thus we see that, after one comma is added, the addition of another does not change the meaning at all, so that whatever has one comma after it must be regarded as having an infinite number.

If, therefore, \(\mathit{l},\!,\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w}\) is not the same as \(\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w}\) (as it plainly is not, because the latter means a lover and servant of a woman, and the former a lover of and servant of and same as a woman), this is simply because the writing of the comma alters the arrangement of the correlates.

And if we are to suppose that absolute terms are multipliers at all (as mathematical generality demands that we should}, we must regard every term as being a relative requiring an infinite number of correlates to its virtual infinite series “that is —— and is —— and is —— etc.”

Now a relative formed by a comma of course receives its subjacent numbers like any relative, but the question is, What are to be the implied subjacent numbers for these implied correlates?

Any term may be regarded as having an infinite number of factors, those at the end being ones, thus:

\(\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathit{w},\!\mathit{1},\!\mathit{1},\!\mathit{1},\!\mathit{1},\!\mathit{1},\!\mathit{1},\!\mathit{1}, ~\text{etc.}\)

A subjacent number may therefore be as great as we please.

But all these ones denote the same identical individual denoted by \(\mathrm{w}\!\); what then can be the subjacent numbers to be applied to \(\mathit{s}\!\), for instance, on account of its infinite “that is”'s? What numbers can separate it from being identical with \(\mathrm{w}\!\)? There are only two. The first is zero, which plainly neutralizes a comma completely, since

\(\mathit{s},_0\!\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{s}\mathrm{w}\)

and the other is infinity; for as \(1^\infty\) is indeterminate in ordinary algbra, so it will be shown hereafter to be here, so that to remove the correlate by the product of an infinite series of ones is to leave it indeterminate.

Accordingly,

\(\mathrm{m},_\infty\)

should be regarded as expressing some man.

Any term, then, is properly to be regarded as having an infinite number of commas, all or some of which are neutralized by zeros.

“Something” may then be expressed by:

\(\mathit{1}_\infty\!\)

I shall for brevity frequently express this by an antique figure one \((\mathfrak{1}).\)

“Anything” by:

\(\mathit{1}_0\!\)

I shall often also write a straight \(1\!\) for anything.

(Peirce, CP 3.73).

Commentary Note 8.1

To my way of thinking, CP 3.73 is one of the most remarkable passages in the history of logic. In this first pass over its deeper contents I won't be able to accord it much more than a superficial dusting off.

Let us imagine a concrete example that will serve in developing the uses of Peirce's notation. Entertain a discourse whose universe \(X\!\) will remind us a little of the cast of characters in Shakespeare's Othello.

\(X ~=~ \{ \mathrm{Bianca}, \mathrm{Cassio}, \mathrm{Clown}, \mathrm{Desdemona}, \mathrm{Emilia}, \mathrm{Iago}, \mathrm{Othello} \}.\)

The universe \(X\!\) is “that class of individuals about which alone the whole discourse is understood to run” but its marking out for special recognition as a universe of discourse in no way rules out the possibility that “discourse may run upon something which is not a subjective part of the universe; for instance, upon the qualities or collections of the individuals it contains” (CP 3.65).

In order to provide ourselves with the convenience of abbreviated terms, while preserving Peirce's conventions about capitalization, we may use the alternate names \(^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{u}^{\prime\prime}\) for the universe \(X\!\) and \(^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{Jeste}^{\prime\prime}\) for the character \(\mathrm{Clown}.~\!\) This permits the above description of the universe of discourse to be rewritten in the following fashion:

\(\mathrm{u} ~=~ \{ \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C}, \mathrm{D}, \mathrm{E}, \mathrm{I}, \mathrm{J}, \mathrm{O} \}\)

This specification of the universe of discourse could be summed up in Peirce's notation by the following equation:

\(\begin{array}{*{15}{c}} \mathbf{1} & = & \mathrm{B} & +\!\!, & \mathrm{C} & +\!\!, & \mathrm{D} & +\!\!, & \mathrm{E} & +\!\!, & \mathrm{I} & +\!\!, & \mathrm{J} & +\!\!, & \mathrm{O} \end{array}\)

Within this discussion, then, the individual terms are as follows:

\(\begin{matrix} ^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{B}^{\prime\prime}, & ^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{C}^{\prime\prime}, & ^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{D}^{\prime\prime}, & ^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{E}^{\prime\prime}, & ^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{I}^{\prime\prime}, & ^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{J}^{\prime\prime}, & ^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{O}^{\prime\prime} \end{matrix}\)

Each of these terms denotes in a singular fashion the corresponding individual in \(X.\!\)

By way of general terms in this discussion, we may begin with the following set:

\(\begin{array}{ccl} ^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{b}^{\prime\prime} & = & ^{\backprime\backprime}\mathrm{black}^{\prime\prime} \'"`UNIQ-MathJax1-QINU`"' <br> {| align="center" cellpadding="10" | [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 7.0.jpg]] || (7) |} {| align="center" cellpadding="10" | [[Image:LOR 1870 Figure 8.0.jpg]] || (8) |} One way to approach the problem of “information fusion” in Peirce's syntax is to soften the distinction between adjacent terms and subjacent signs and to treat the types of constraints that they separately signify more on a par with each other. To that purpose, I will set forth a way of thinking about relational composition that emphasizes the set-theoretic constraints involved in the construction of a composite. For example, suppose that we are given the relations \(L \subseteq X \times Y\) and \(M \subseteq Y \times Z.\) Table 9 and Figure 10 present two ways of picturing the constraints that are involved in constructing the relational composition \(L \circ M \subseteq X \times Z.\)


\(\text{Table 9.} ~~ \text{Relational Composition}\!\)
  \(\mathit{1}\!\) \(\mathit{1}\!\) \(\mathit{1}\!\)
\(L\!\) \(X\!\) \(Y\!\)  
\(M\!\)   \(Y\!\) \(Z\!\)
\(L \circ M\!\) \(X\!\)   \(Z\!\)


The way to read Table 9 is to imagine that you are playing a game that involves placing tokens on the squares of a board that is marked in just this way. The rules are that you have to place a single token on each marked square in the middle of the board in such a way that all of the indicated constraints are satisfied. That is to say, you have to place a token whose denomination is a value in the set \(X\!\) on each of the squares marked \({}^{\backprime\backprime} X {}^{\prime\prime},\) and similarly for the squares marked \({}^{\backprime\backprime} Y {}^{\prime\prime}\) and \({}^{\backprime\backprime} Z {}^{\prime\prime},\) meanwhile leaving all of the blank squares empty. Furthermore, the tokens placed in each row and column have to obey the relational constraints that are indicated at the heads of the corresponding row and column. Thus, the two tokens from \(X\!\) have to denominate the very same value from \(X,\!\) and likewise for \(Y\!\) and \(Z,\!\) while the pairs of tokens on the rows marked \({}^{\backprime\backprime} L {}^{\prime\prime}\) and \({}^{\backprime\backprime} M {}^{\prime\prime}\) are required to denote elements that are in the relations \(L\!\) and \(M,\!\) respectively. The upshot is that when just this much is done, that is, when the \(L,\!\) \(M,\!\) and \(\mathit{1}\!\) relations are satisfied, then the row marked \({}^{\backprime\backprime} L \circ M {}^{\prime\prime}\) will automatically bear the tokens of a pair of elements in the composite relation \(L \circ M.\!\)

Figure 10 shows a different way of viewing the same situation.


File:LOR 1870 Figure 10.jpg (10)

Commentary Note 10.3

I will devote some time to drawing out the relationships that exist among the different pictures of relations and relative terms that were shown above, or as redrawn here:


File:LOR 1870 Figure 7.0.jpg (11)
File:LOR 1870 Figure 8.0.jpg (12)

Figures 11 and 12 present examples of relative multiplication in one of the styles of syntax that Peirce used, to which I added lines of identity to connect the corresponding marks of reference. These pictures are adapted to showing the anatomy of relative terms, while the forms of analysis illustrated in Table 13 and Figure 14 are designed to highlight the structures of the objective relations themselves.


\(\text{Table 13.} ~~ \text{Relational Composition}\!\)
  \(\mathit{1}\!\) \(\mathit{1}\!\) \(\mathit{1}\!\)
\(L\!\) \(X\!\) \(Y\!\)  
\(S\!\)   \(Y\!\) \(Z\!\)
\(L \circ S\!\) \(X\!\)   \(Z\!\)


File:LOR 1870 Figure 14.jpg (14)

There are many ways that Peirce might have gotten from his 1870 Notation for the Logic of Relatives to his more evolved systems of Logical Graphs. It is interesting to speculate on how the metamorphosis might have been accomplished by way of transformations that act on these nascent forms of syntax and that take place not too far from the pale of its means, that is, as nearly as possible according to the rules and the permissions of the initial system itself.

In Existential Graphs, a relation is represented by a node whose degree is the adicity of that relation, and which is adjacent via lines of identity to the nodes that represent its correlative relations, including as a special case any of its terminal individual arguments.

In the 1870 Logic of Relatives, implicit lines of identity are invoked by the subjacent numbers and marks of reference only when a correlate of some relation is the relate of some relation. Thus, the principal relate, which is not a correlate of any explicit relation, is not singled out in this way.

Remarkably enough, the comma modifier itself provides us with a mechanism to abstract the logic of relations from the logic of relatives, and thus to forge a possible link between the syntax of relative terms and the more graphical depiction of the objective relations themselves.

Figure 15 demonstrates this possibility, posing a transitional case between the style of syntax in Figure 11 and the picture of composition in Figure 14.


File:LOR 1870 Figure 15.jpg (15)

In this composite sketch the diagonal extension \(\mathit{1}\!\) of the universe \(\mathbf{1}\!\) is invoked up front to anchor an explicit line of identity for the leading relate of the composition, while the terminal argument \(\mathrm{w}\!\) has been generalized to the whole universe \(\mathbf{1},\!\) in effect, executing an act of abstraction. This type of universal bracketing isolates the composing of the relations \(L\!\) and \(S\!\) to form the composite \(L \circ S.\!\) The three relational domains \(X, Y, Z\!\) may be distinguished from one another, or else rolled up into a single universe of discourse, as one prefers.

Commentary Note 10.4

From now on I will use the forms of analysis exemplified in the last set of Figures and Tables as a routine bridge between the logic of relative terms and the logic of their extended relations. For future reference, we may think of Table 13 as illustrating the spreadsheet model of relational composition, while Figure 14 may be thought of as making a start toward a hypergraph model of generalized compositions. I will explain the hypergraph model in some detail at a later point. The transitional form of analysis represented by Figure 15 may be called the universal bracketing of relatives as relations.

Commentary Note 10.5

We have sufficiently covered the application of the comma functor, or the diagonal extension, to absolute terms, so let us return to where we were in working our way through CP 3.73 and see whether we can validate Peirce's statements about the “commifications” of 2-adic relative terms that yield their 3-adic diagonal extensions.

But not only may any absolute term be thus regarded as a relative term, but any relative term may in the same way be regarded as a relative with one correlate more. It is convenient to take this additional correlate as the first one.

Then:

\(\mathit{l},\!\mathit{s}\mathrm{w}\)

will denote a lover of a woman that is a servant of that woman.

The comma here after \(\mathit{l}\!\) should not be considered as altering at all the meaning of \(\mathit{l}\!\), but as only a subjacent sign, serving to alter the arrangement of the correlates.

(Peirce, CP 3.73).

Just to plant our feet on a more solid stage, let's apply this idea to the Othello example. For this performance only, just to make the example more interesting, let us assume that \(\mathrm{Jeste ~ (J)}\!\) is secretly in love with \(\mathrm{Desdemona ~ (D)}.\!\)

Then we begin with the modified data set:

\(\begin{array}{*{15}{c}} \mathrm{w} & = & \mathrm{B} & +\!\!, & \mathrm{D} & +\!\!, & \mathrm{E} \'"`UNIQ-MathJax2-QINU`"' ==='"`UNIQ--h-73--QINU`"'Commentary Note 11.14=== Now, as promised, let's look at a more homely example of a morphism, say, any one of the mappings \(J : \mathbb{R} \to \mathbb{R}\!\) (roughly speaking) that are commonly known as logarithm functions, where you get to pick your favorite base. In this case, \(K(r, s) = r + s~\!\) and \(L(u, v) = u \cdot v,\!\) and the defining formula \(J(L(u, v)) = K(Ju, Jv)\!\) comes out looking like \(J(u \cdot v) = J(u) + J(v),\!\) writing a dot \((\cdot)~\!\) and a plus sign \((+)\!\) for the ordinary binary operations of arithmetical multiplication and arithmetical summation, respectively.


File:LOR 1870 Figure 49.jpg (49)

Thus, where the image \(J\!\) is the logarithm map, the compound \(K\!\) is the numerical sum, and the ligature \(L\!\) is the numerical product, one has the following rule of thumb:

\(\textit{The~image~of~the~product~is~the~sum~of~the~images.}\)

\(\begin{array}{lll} J(u \cdot v) & = & J(u) + J(v) \'"`UNIQ-MathJax3-QINU`"' So let us try to uncross Peirce's manifestly chiasmatic encryption of the condition that is called on in support of this preservation. The proviso for the equation \([xy] = [x][y]\!\) to hold is this:

There are just as many \(x\!\)'s per \(y\!\) as there are per things, things of the universe.

(Peirce, CP 3.76).

Returning to the example that Peirce gives:

NOF 4.2

For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there are as many teeth to a Frenchman (perfect understood) as there are to any one of the universe, then:

\([\mathit{t}][\mathrm{f}] ~=~ [\mathit{t}\mathrm{f}]\)

holds arithmetically.

(Peirce, CP 3.76).

Now that is something that we can sink our teeth into and trace the bigraph representation of the situation. It will help to recall our first examination of the “tooth of” relation and to adjust the picture we sketched of it on that occasion.

Transcribing Peirce's example:

Let \(\mathrm{m} = \text{man}\!\)  
 
and \(\mathit{t} = \text{tooth of}\,\underline{~~ ~~}.\!\)  
 
Then \(v(\mathit{t}) ~=~ [\mathit{t}] ~=~ \frac{[\mathit{t}\mathrm{m}]}{[\mathrm{m}]}.\!\)  

That is to say, the number of the relative term \(\text{tooth of}\,\underline{~~ ~~}\!\) is equal to the number of teeth of humans divided by the number of humans. In a universe of perfect human dentition this gives a quotient of \(32.\!\)

The dyadic relative term \(t\!\) determines a dyadic relation \(T \subseteq X \times Y,\) where \(X\!\) contains all the teeth and \(Y\!\) contains all the people that happen to be under discussion.

To make the case as simple as possible and still cover the point, suppose there are just four people in our universe of discourse and just two of them are French. The bigraphical composition below shows the pertinent facts of the case.

File:LOR 1870 Figure 52.jpg (52)

In this picture the order of relational composition flows down the page. For convenience in composing relations, the absolute term \(\mathrm{f} = \text{Frenchman}\!\) is inflected by the comma functor to form the dyadic relative term \(\mathrm{f,} = \text{Frenchman that is}\,\underline{~~ ~~},\!\) which in turn determines the idempotent representation of Frenchmen as a subset of mankind, \(F \subseteq Y \times Y.\!\)

By way of a legend for the figure, we have the following data:

\(\begin{array}{lllr} \mathrm{m} & = & \mathrm{J} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{K} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{L} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{M} \qquad = & \mathbf{1} \'"`UNIQ-MathJax4-QINU`"' and \(\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}) = \frac{1}{7}.\)

If these were independent terms we would have\[\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m}\mathrm{b}) = \frac{4}{49}.\]

In point of fact, however, we have\[\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{m}\mathrm{b}) = \mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}) = \frac{1}{7}.\]

Another way to see it is to observe that\[\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}|\mathrm{m}) = \frac{1}{4}\] while \(\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}) = \frac{1}{7}.\)

Commentary Note 11.23

Peirce's description of logical conjunction and conditional probability via the logic of relatives and the mathematics of relations is critical to understanding the relationship between logic and measurement, in effect, the qualitative and quantitative aspects of inquiry. To ground this connection firmly in mind, I will try to sum up as succinctly as possible, in more current notation, the lesson we ought to take away from Peirce's last “number of” example, since I know the account I have given so far may appear to have wandered widely.

NOF 4.4

So if men are just as apt to be black as things in general,

\([\mathrm{m,}][\mathrm{b}] ~=~ [\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}],\!\)

where the difference between \([\mathrm{m}]\!\) and \([\mathrm{m,}]\!\) must not be overlooked.

(Peirce, CP 3.76).

In different lights the formula \([\mathrm{m,}\mathrm{b}] = [\mathrm{m,}][\mathrm{b}]\!\) presents itself as an aimed arrow, fair sampling, or statistical independence condition. The concept of independence was illustrated above by means of a case where independence fails. The details of that counterexample are summarized below.

File:LOR 1870 Figure 53.jpg (54)

The condition that “men are just as apt to be black as things in general” is expressed in terms of conditional probabilities as \(\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}|\mathrm{m}) = \mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}),\!\) which means that the probability of the event \(\mathrm{b}\!\) given the event \(\mathrm{m}\!\) is equal to the unconditional probability of the event \(\mathrm{b}.\!\)

In the Othello example, it is enough to observe that \(\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}|\mathrm{m}) = \tfrac{1}{4}\!\) while \(\mathrm{P}(\mathrm{b}) = \tfrac{1}{7}\!\) in order to recognize the bias or dependency of the sampling map.

The reduction of a conditional probability to an absolute probability, as \(\mathrm{P}(A|Z) = \mathrm{P}(A),\!\) is one of the ways we come to recognize the condition of independence, \(\mathrm{P}(AZ) = \mathrm{P}(A)P(Z),\!\) via the definition of conditional probability, \(\mathrm{P}(A|Z) = \displaystyle{\mathrm{P}(AZ) \over \mathrm{P}(Z)}.\!\)

To recall the derivation, the definition of conditional probability plus the independence condition yields \(\mathrm{P}(A|Z) = \displaystyle{\mathrm{P}(AZ) \over P(Z)} = \displaystyle{\mathrm{P}(A)\mathrm{P}(Z) \over \mathrm{P}(Z)},\!\) in short, \(\mathrm{P}(A|Z) = \mathrm{P}(A).\!\)

As Hamlet discovered, there's a lot to be learned from turning a crank.

Commentary Note 11.24

We come to the end of the “number of” examples that we found on our agenda at this point in the text:

NOF 4.5

It is to be observed that

\([\mathit{1}] ~=~ 1.\)

Boole was the first to show this connection between logic and probabilities. He was restricted, however, to absolute terms. I do not remember having seen any extension of probability to relatives, except the ordinary theory of expectation.

Our logical multiplication, then, satisfies the essential conditions of multiplication, has a unity, has a conception similar to that of admitted multiplications, and contains numerical multiplication as a case under it.

(Peirce, CP 3.76 and CE 2, 376).

There are problems with the printing of the text at this point. Let us first recall the conventions we are using in this transcription, in particular, \(\mathit{1}\!\) for the italic 1 that signifies the dyadic identity relation and \(\mathfrak{1}\) for the “antique figure one” that Peirce defines as \(\mathit{1}_\infty = \text{something}.\)

CP 3 gives \([\mathit{1}] = \mathfrak{1},\) which I cannot make sense of. CE 2 gives the 1's in different styles of italics, but reading the equation as \([\mathit{1}] = 1,\!\) makes the best sense if the “1” on the right hand side is read as the numeral “1” that denotes the natural number 1, and not as the absolute term “1” that denotes the universe of discourse. Read this way, \([\mathit{1}]\!\) is the average number of things related by the identity relation \(\mathit{1}\!\) to one individual, and so it makes sense that \([\mathit{1}] = 1 \in \mathbb{N},\) where \(\mathbb{N}\) is the set of non-negative integers \(\{ 0, 1, 2, \ldots \}.\)

With respect to the relative term \(^{\backprime\backprime} \mathit{1} ^{\prime\prime}\) in the syntactic domain \(S\!\) and the number \(1\!\) in the non-negative integers \(\mathbb{N} \subset \mathbb{R},\) we have:

\(v(\mathit{1}) ~=~ [\mathit{1}] ~=~ 1.\)

And so the “number of” mapping \(v : S \to \mathbb{R}\) has another one of the properties that would be required of an arrow \(S \to \mathbb{R}.\)

The manner in which these arrows and qualified arrows help us to construct a suspension bridge that unifies logic, semiotics, statistics, stochastics, and information theory will be one of the main themes I aim to elaborate throughout the rest of this inquiry.

Selection 12

The Sign of Involution

I shall take involution in such a sense that \(x^y\!\) will denote everything which is an \(x\!\) for every individual of \(y.\!\)  Thus \(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!\) will be a lover of every woman.  Then \((\mathit{s}^\mathit{l})^\mathrm{w}\!\) will denote whatever stands to every woman in the relation of servant of every lover of hers;  and \(\mathit{s}^{(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})}\!\) will denote whatever is a servant of everything that is lover of a woman.  So that

\((\mathit{s}^\mathit{l})^\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{s}^{(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})}.\!\)

(Peirce, CP 3.77).

Commentary Note 12.1

To get a better sense of why the above formulas mean what they do, and to prepare the ground for understanding more complex relational expressions, it will help to assemble the following materials and definitions:

\(X\!\) is a set singled out in a particular discussion as the universe of discourse.
\(W \subseteq X\!\) is the 1-adic relation, or set, whose elements fall under the absolute term \(\mathrm{w} = \text{woman}.\!\) The elements of \(W\!\) are sometimes referred to as the denotation or the set-theoretic extension of the term \(\mathrm{w}.\!\)
\(L \subseteq X \times X\!\) is the 2-adic relation associated with the relative term \(\mathit{l} = \text{lover of}\,\underline{~~ ~~}.\!\)
\(S \subseteq X \times X\!\) is the 2-adic relation associated with the relative term \(\mathit{s} = \text{servant of}\,\underline{~~ ~~}.\!\)
\(\mathsf{W} = (\mathsf{W}_x) = \mathrm{Mat}(W) = \mathrm{Mat}(\mathrm{w})\) is the 1-dimensional matrix representation of the set \(W\!\) and the term \(\mathrm{w}.\!\)
\(\mathsf{L} = (\mathsf{L}_{xy}) = \mathrm{Mat}(L) = \mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{l})~\!\) is the 2-dimensional matrix representation of the relation \(L\!\) and the relative term \(\mathit{l}.\!\)
\(\mathsf{S} = (\mathsf{S}_{xy}) = \mathrm{Mat}(S) = \mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{s})\!\) is the 2-dimensional matrix representation of the relation \(S\!\) and the relative term \(\mathit{s}.~\!\)

Recalling a few definitions, the local flags of the relation \(L\!\) are given as follows:

\(\begin{array}{lll} u \star L & = & L_{u \,\text{at}\, 1} \\[6pt] & = & \{ (u, x) \in L \} \\[6pt] & = & \text{the ordered pairs in}~ L ~\text{that have}~ u ~\text{in the 1st place}. \\[9pt] L \star v & = & L_{v \,\text{at}\, 2} \\[6pt] & = & \{ (x, v) \in L \} \\[6pt] & = & \text{the ordered pairs in}~ L ~\text{that have}~ v ~\text{in the 2nd place}. \end{array}\!\)

The applications of the relation \(L\!\) are defined as follows:

\(\begin{array}{lll} u \cdot L & = & \mathrm{proj}_2 (u \star L) \\[6pt] & = & \{ x \in X : (u, x) \in L \} \\[6pt] & = & \text{loved by}~ u. \\[9pt] L \cdot v & = & \mathrm{proj}_1 (L \star v) \\[6pt] & = & \{ x \in X : (x, v) \in L \} \\[6pt] & = & \text{lover of}~ v. \end{array}\!\)

Commentary Note 12.2

Let us make a few preliminary observations about the operation of logical involution, as Peirce introduces it here:

I shall take involution in such a sense that \(x^y\!\) will denote everything which is an \(x\!\) for every individual of \(y.\!\)  Thus \(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!\) will be a lover of every woman.

(Peirce, CP 3.77).

In ordinary arithmetic the involution \(x^y,\!\) or the exponentiation of \(x\!\) to the power of \(y,\!\) is the repeated application of the multiplier \(x\!\) for as many times as there are ones making up the exponent \(y.\!\)

In analogous fashion, the logical involution \(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!\) is the repeated application of the term \(\mathit{l}\!\) for as many times as there are individuals under the term \(\mathrm{w}.\!\) According to Peirce's interpretive rules, the repeated applications of the base term \(\mathit{l}\!\) are distributed across the individuals of the exponent term \(\mathrm{w}.\!\) In particular, the base term \(\mathit{l}\!\) is not applied successively in the manner that would give something like “a lover of a lover of … a lover of a woman”.

For example, suppose that a universe of discourse numbers among its contents just three women, \(\mathrm{W}^{\prime}, \mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime}, \mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime\prime}.\) This could be expressed in Peirce's notation by writing:

\(\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathrm{W}^{\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime\prime}\)

Under these circumstances the following equation would hold:

\(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{l}^{(\mathrm{W}^{\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime} ~+\!\!,~ \mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime\prime})} ~=~ (\mathit{l}\mathrm{W}^{\prime}), (\mathit{l}\mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime}), (\mathit{l}\mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime\prime}).\)

This says that a lover of every woman in the given universe of discourse is a lover of \(\mathrm{W}^{\prime}\) that is a lover of \(\mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime}\) that is a lover of \(\mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime\prime}.\) In other words, a lover of every woman in this context is a lover of \(\mathrm{W}^{\prime}\) and a lover of \(\mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime}\) and a lover of \(\mathrm{W}^{\prime\prime\prime}.\)

The denotation of the term \(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!\) is a subset of \(X\!\) that can be obtained as follows: For each flag of the form \(L \star x\!\) with \(x \in W,\!\) collect the elements \(\mathrm{proj}_1 (L \star x)~\!\) that appear as the first components of these ordered pairs, and then take the intersection of all these subsets. Putting it all together:

\(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w} ~=~ \bigcap_{x \in W} \mathrm{proj}_1 (L \star x) ~=~ \bigcap_{x \in W} L \cdot x\)

It is very instructive to examine the matrix representation of \(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!\) at this point, not the least because it effectively dispels the mystery of the name involution. First, let us make the following observation. To say that \(j\!\) is a lover of every woman is to say that \(j\!\) loves \(k\!\) if \(k\!\) is a woman. This can be rendered in symbols as follows:

\(j ~\text{loves}~ k ~\Leftarrow~ k ~\text{is a woman}\)

Reading the formula \(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!\) as “\(j\!\) loves \(k\!\) if \(k\!\) is a woman” highlights the operation of converse implication inherent in it, and this in turn reveals the analogy between implication and involution that accounts for the aptness of the latter name.

The operations defined by the formulas   \(x^y = z\!\)   and   \((x\!\Leftarrow\!y) = z\)   for \(x, y, z \in \mathbb{B} = \{ 0, 1 \}\) are tabulated below:

\( \begin{array}{ccc} x^y & = & z \\ \hline 0^0 & = & 1 \\ 0^1 & = & 0 \\ 1^0 & = & 1 \\ 1^1 & = & 1 \end{array} \qquad\qquad\qquad \begin{array}{ccc} x\!\Leftarrow\!y & = & z \\ \hline 0\!\Leftarrow\!0 & = & 1 \\ 0\!\Leftarrow\!1 & = & 0 \\ 1\!\Leftarrow\!0 & = & 1 \\ 1\!\Leftarrow\!1 & = & 1 \end{array} \)

It is clear that these operations are isomorphic, amounting to the same operation of type \(\mathbb{B} \times \mathbb{B} \to \mathbb{B}.\!\) All that remains is to see how this operation on coefficient values in \(\mathbb{B}\!\) induces the corresponding operations on sets and terms.

The term \(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!\) determines a selection of individuals from the universe of discourse \(X\!\) that may be computed by means of the corresponding operation on coefficient matrices. If the terms \(\mathit{l}\!\) and \(\mathrm{w}\!\) are represented by the matrices \(\mathsf{L} = \mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{l})\) and \(\mathsf{W} = \mathrm{Mat}(\mathrm{w}),\) respectively, then the operation on terms that produces the term \(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!\) must be represented by a corresponding operation on matrices, say, \(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W} = \mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{l})^{\mathrm{Mat}(\mathrm{w})},\) that produces the matrix \(\mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}).\) In other words, the involution operation on matrices must be defined in such a way that the following equations hold:

\(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W} ~=~ \mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{l})^{\mathrm{Mat}(\mathrm{w})} ~=~ \mathrm{Mat}(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w})\!\)

The fact that \(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!\) denotes the elements of a subset of \(X\!\) means that the matrix \(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W}\!\) is a 1-dimensional array of coefficients in \(\mathbb{B}\!\) that is indexed by the elements of \(X.\!\) The value of the matrix \(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W}\!\) at the index \({u \in X}\!\) is written \((\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_u\!\) and computed as follows:

\((\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_u ~=~ \prod_{v \in X} \mathsf{L}_{uv}^{\mathsf{W}_v}\!\)

Commentary Note 12.3

We now have two ways of computing a logical involution that raises a dyadic relative term to the power of a monadic absolute term, for example, \(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!\) for “lover of every woman”.

The first method operates in the medium of set theory, expressing the denotation of the term \(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!\) as the intersection of a set of relational applications:

\(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w} ~=~ \bigcap_{x \in W} L \cdot x\!\)

The second method operates in the matrix representation, expressing the value of the matrix \(\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W}\!\) with respect to an argument \(u\!\) as a product of coefficient powers:

\((\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_u ~=~ \prod_{v \in X} \mathsf{L}_{uv}^{\mathsf{W}_v}\!\)

Abstract formulas like these are more easily grasped with the aid of a concrete example and a picture of the relations involved.

Example 6

Consider a universe of discourse \(X\!\) that is subject to the following data:

\(\begin{array}{*{15}{c}} X & = & \{ & a, & b, & c, & d, & e, & f, & g, & h, & i & \} \\[6pt] W & = & \{ & d, & f & \} \\[6pt] L & = & \{ & b\!:\!a, & b\!:\!c, & c\!:\!b, & c\!:\!d, & e\!:\!d, & e\!:\!e, & e\!:\!f, & g\!:\!f, & g\!:\!h, & h\!:\!g, & h\!:\!i & \} \end{array}\)

Figure 55 shows the placement of \(W\!\) within \(X\!\) and the placement of \(L\!\) within \(X \times X.\!\)

  File:LOR 1870 Figure 55.jpg (55)

To highlight the role of \(W\!\) more clearly, the Figure represents the absolute term \({}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{w} {}^{\prime\prime}\!\) by means of the relative term \({}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{w}, \! {}^{\prime\prime}\!\) that conveys the same information.

Computing the denotation of \(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w}\!\) by way of the set-theoretic formula, we can show our work as follows:

\(\mathit{l}^\mathrm{w} ~=~ \bigcap_{x \in W} L \cdot x ~=~ L \cdot d ~\cap~ L \cdot f ~=~ \{ c, e \} \cap \{ e, g \} ~=~ \{ e \}\)

With the above Figure in mind, we can visualize the computation of \((\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_u = \textstyle\prod_{v \in X} \mathsf{L}_{uv}^{\mathsf{W}_v}\!\) as follows:

1. Pick a specific \(u\!\) in the bottom row of the Figure.
2. Pan across the elements \(v\!\) in the middle row of the Figure.
3. If \(u\!\) links to \(v\!\) then \(\mathsf{L}_{uv} = 1,\!\) otherwise \({\mathsf{L}_{uv} = 0}.\!\)
4. If \(v\!\) in the middle row links to \(v\!\) in the top row then \(\mathsf{W}_v = 1,\!\) otherwise \(\mathsf{W}_v = 0.\!\)
5. Compute the value \(\mathsf{L}_{uv}^{\mathsf{W}_v} = (\mathsf{L}_{uv} \Leftarrow \mathsf{W}_v)\!\) for each \(v\!\) in the middle row.
6. If any of the values \(\mathsf{L}_{uv}^{\mathsf{W}_v}\!\) is \(0\!\) then the product \(\textstyle\prod_{v \in X} \mathsf{L}_{uv}^{\mathsf{W}_v}\!\) is \(0,\!\) otherwise it is \(1.\!\)

As a general observation, we know that the value of \((\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_u\!\) goes to \(0~\!\) just as soon as we find a \(v \in X\!\) such that \(\mathsf{L}_{uv} = 0\!\) and \(\mathsf{W}_v = 1,\!\) in other words, such that \((u, v) \notin L\!\) but \(v \in W.\!\) If there is no such \(v\!\) then \((\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_u = 1.\!\)

Running through the program for each \(u \in X,\!\) the only case that produces a non-zero result is \((\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_e = 1.\!\) That portion of the work can be sketched as follows:

\((\mathsf{L}^\mathsf{W})_e ~=~ \prod_{v \in X} \mathsf{L}_{ev}^{\mathsf{W}_v} ~=~ 0^0 \cdot 0^0 \cdot 0^0 \cdot 1^1 \cdot 1^0 \cdot 1^1 \cdot 0^0 \cdot 0^0 \cdot 0^0 ~=~ 1\!\)

Commentary Note 12.4

Peirce next considers a pair of compound involutions, stating an equation between them that is analogous to a law of exponents in ordinary arithmetic, namely, \((a^b)^c = a^{bc}.\!\)

Then \((\mathit{s}^\mathit{l})^\mathrm{w}\!\) will denote whatever stands to every woman in the relation of servant of every lover of hers;  and \(\mathit{s}^{(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})}\!\) will denote whatever is a servant of everything that is lover of a woman.  So that

\((\mathit{s}^\mathit{l})^\mathrm{w} ~=~ \mathit{s}^{(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})}.\!\)

(Peirce, CP 3.77).

Articulating the compound relative term \(\mathit{s}^{(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})}\!\) in set-theoretic terms is fairly immediate:

\(\mathit{s}^{(\mathit{l}\mathrm{w})} ~=~ \bigcap_{x \in LW} \mathrm{proj}_1 (S \star x) ~=~ \bigcap_{x \in LW} S \cdot x\!\)

On the other hand, translating the compound relative term \((\mathit{s}^\mathit{l})^\mathrm{w}\!\) into a set-theoretic equivalent is less immediate, the hang-up being that we have yet to define the case of logical involution that raises a dyadic relative term to the power of a dyadic relative term. As a result, it looks easier to proceed through the matrix representation, drawing once again on the inspection of a concrete example.

Example 7

\(\begin{array}{*{15}{c}} X & = & \{ & a, & b, & c, & d, & e, & f, & g, & h, & i\ & \} \\[6pt] L & = & \{ & b\!:\!a, & b\!:\!c, & c\!:\!b, & c\!:\!d, & e\!:\!d, & e\!:\!e, & e\!:\!f, & g\!:\!f, & g\!:\!h, & h\!:\!g, & h\!:\!i & \} \\[6pt] S & = & \{ & b\!:\!a, & b\!:\!c, & d\!:\!c, & d\!:\!d, & d\!:\!e, & f\!:\!e, & f\!:\!f, & f\!:\!g, & h\!:\!g, & h\!:\!i\ & \} \end{array}\)

  File:LOR 1870 Figure 56.jpg (56)

There is a “servant of every lover of” link between \(u\!\) and \(v\!\) if and only if \(u \cdot S ~\supseteq~ L \cdot v.\!\)  But the vacuous inclusions, that is, the cases where \(L \cdot v = \varnothing,\!\) have the effect of adding non-intuitive links to the mix.

The computational requirements are evidently met by the following formula:

\((\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})_{xy} ~=~ \prod_{p \in X} \mathsf{S}_{xp}^{\mathsf{L}_{py}}\!\)

In other words, \((\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})_{xy} = 0\!\) if and only if there exists a \({p \in X}\!\) such that \(\mathsf{S}_{xp} = 0\!\) and \(\mathsf{L}_{py} = 1.\!\)

Commentary Note 12.5

The equation \((\mathit{s}^\mathit{l})^\mathrm{w} = \mathit{s}^{\mathit{l}\mathrm{w}}\!\) can be verified by establishing the corresponding equation in matrices:

\((\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})^\mathsf{W} ~=~ \mathsf{S}^{\mathsf{L}\mathsf{W}}\)

If \(\mathsf{A}\) and \(\mathsf{B}\) are two 1-dimensional matrices over the same index set \(X\!\) then \(\mathsf{A} = \mathsf{B}\) if and only if \(\mathsf{A}_x = \mathsf{B}_x\) for every \(x \in X.\) Thus, a routine way to check the validity of \((\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})^\mathsf{W} = \mathsf{S}^{\mathsf{L}\mathsf{W}}\) is to check whether the following equation holds for arbitrary \(x \in X.\)

\(((\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})^\mathsf{W})_x ~=~ (\mathsf{S}^{\mathsf{L}\mathsf{W}})_x\)

Taking both ends toward the middle, we proceed as follows:

\( \begin{array}{*{7}{l}} ((\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})^\mathsf{W})_x & = & \displaystyle \prod_{p \in X} (\mathsf{S}^\mathsf{L})_{xp}^{\mathsf{W}_p} & = & \displaystyle \prod_{p \in X} (\prod_{q \in X} \mathsf{S}_{xq}^{\mathsf{L}_{qp}})^{\mathsf{W}_p} & = & \displaystyle \prod_{p \in X} \prod_{q \in X} \mathsf{S}_{xq}^{\mathsf{L}_{qp}\mathsf{W}_p} \\[36px] (\mathsf{S}^{\mathsf{L}\mathsf{W}})_x & = & \displaystyle \prod_{q \in X} \mathsf{S}_{xq}^{(\mathsf{L}\mathsf{W})_q} & = & \displaystyle \prod_{q \in X} \mathsf{S}_{xq}^{\sum_{p \in X} \mathsf{L}_{qp} \mathsf{W}_p} & = & \displaystyle \prod_{q \in X} \prod_{p \in X} \mathsf{S}_{xq}^{\mathsf{L}_{qp} \mathsf{W}_p} \end{array} \)

The products commute, so the equation holds. In essence, the matrix identity turns on the fact that the law of exponents \((a^b)^c = a^{bc}\!\) in ordinary arithmetic holds when the values \(a, b, c\!\) are restricted to the boolean domain \(\mathbb{B} = \{ 0, 1 \}.\) Interpreted as a logical statement, the law of exponents \((a^b)^c = a^{bc}\!\) amounts to a theorem of propositional calculus that is otherwise expressed in the following ways:

\(\begin{matrix} (a \,\Leftarrow\, b) \,\Leftarrow\, c & = & a \,\Leftarrow\, b \land c \\[8pt] (a >\!\!\!-~ b) >\!\!\!-~ c & = & a >\!\!\!-~ bc \\[8pt] c ~-\!\!\!< (b ~-\!\!\!< a) & = & cb ~-\!\!\!< a \\[8pt] c \,\Rightarrow\, (b \,\Rightarrow\, a) & = & c \land b \,\Rightarrow\, a \end{matrix}\)

Commentary Note 12.6

References

  • Boole, George (1854), An Investigation of the Laws of Thought, On Which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities, Macmillan, 1854. Reprinted, Dover Publications, New York, NY, 1958.
  • Peirce, C.S. (1870), “Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives, Resulting from an Amplification of the Conceptions of Boole's Calculus of Logic”, Memoirs of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences 9, 317–378, 26 January 1870. Reprinted, Collected Papers (CP 3.45–149), Chronological Edition (CE 2, 359–429). Online (1) (2) (3).
  • Peirce, C.S., Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1–6, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (eds.), vols. 7–8, Arthur W. Burks (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1931–1935, 1958. Cited as (CP volume.paragraph).
  • Peirce, C.S., Writings of Charles S. Peirce : A Chronological Edition, Peirce Edition Project (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianoplis, IN, 1981–. Cited as (CE volume, page).

Further Reading

  • Brady, G. (2000), From Peirce to Skolem : A Neglected Chapter in the History of Logic, Elsevier, Amsterdam. Online Preview.
  • Lambek, J., and Scott, P.J. (1986), Introduction to Higher Order Categorical Logic, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
  • Mili, A., Desharnais, J., Mili, F., with Frappier, M. (1994), Computer Program Construction, Oxford University Press, New York, NY.
  • Walsh, A. (2012), Relations Between Logic and Mathematics in the Work of Benjamin and Charles S. Peirce, Docent Press, Boston, MA.

See Also

Template:Col-breakTemplate:Col-breakTemplate:Col-end