Difference between revisions of "Hypostatic abstraction"
Jon Awbrey (talk | contribs) (→External links: Hypostatic Abstraction → ThoughtMesh) |
Jon Awbrey (talk | contribs) (→See also: column template) |
||
Line 44: | Line 44: | ||
==See also== | ==See also== | ||
− | { | + | |
− | + | {{col-begin}} | |
+ | {{col-break}} | ||
* [[Abstraction]] | * [[Abstraction]] | ||
* [[Abstraction (computer science)|Abstraction in computing]] | * [[Abstraction (computer science)|Abstraction in computing]] | ||
Line 51: | Line 52: | ||
* [[Analogy]] | * [[Analogy]] | ||
* [[Category theory]] | * [[Category theory]] | ||
− | + | {{col-break}} | |
* [[Continuous predicate]] | * [[Continuous predicate]] | ||
* [[Hypostatic object]] | * [[Hypostatic object]] | ||
Line 57: | Line 58: | ||
* [[Reification]] | * [[Reification]] | ||
* [[E-prime]] | * [[E-prime]] | ||
− | + | {{col-end}} | |
==External links== | ==External links== |
Revision as of 20:22, 12 March 2008
Hypostatic abstraction, also known as hypostasis or subjectal abstraction, is a formal operation that takes an element of information, such as might be expressed in a proposition of the form X is Y, and conceives its information to consist in the relation between a subject and another subject, such as expressed in a proposition of the form X has Y-ness. The existence of the latter subject, here Y-ness, consists solely in the truth of those propositions that have the corresponding concrete term, here Y, as the predicate. The object of discussion or thought thus introduced may also be called a hypostatic object.
The above definition is adapted from the one given by Charles Sanders Peirce (CP 4.235, "The Simplest Mathematics" (1902), in Collected Papers, CP 4.227–323).
The way that Peirce describes it, the main thing about the formal operation of hypostatic abstraction, insofar as it can be observed to operate on formal linguistic expressions, is that it converts an adjective or some part of a predicate into an extra subject, upping the arity, also called the adicity, of the main predicate in the process.
For example, a typical case of hypostatic abstraction occurs in the transformation from "honey is sweet" to "honey possesses sweetness", which transformation can be viewed in the following variety of ways:
o-----------------------------------------------------------o | | | Hypostasis | | Sweet(honey) ---------------> Possesses(honey, sweetness) | | | o-----------------------------------------------------------o | | | S(h) ------------> P(h , s) | | | o-----------------------------------------------------------o | | | S P | | o ------------> o | | | | | | o o | | h <h , s> | | | o-----------------------------------------------------------o | | | ^ | | [S] ------------> /P\ | | | o---o | | | | | | | o o o | | h h s | | | o-----------------------------------------------------------o
The grammatical trace of this hypostatic transformation tells of a process that abstracts the adjective "sweet" from the main predicate "is sweet", thus arriving at a new, increased-arity predicate "possesses", and as a by-product of the reaction, as it were, precipitating out the substantive "sweetness" as a new second subject of the new predicate, "possesses".
References
- Peirce, C.S., Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1–6, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (eds.), vols. 7–8, Arthur W. Burks (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1931–1935, 1958.
See also
Template:Col-breakTemplate:Col-breakTemplate:Col-endExternal links
Aficionados
- See Talk:Hypostatic abstraction for discussions/comments regarding this article.
- See Hypostatic abstraction/Aficionados for those who have listed Hypostatic abstraction as an interest.
- See Talk:Hypostatic abstraction/Aficionados for discussions regarding this interest.
<sharethis />